without most
footnotes
Summary. The
article defends the stance of moral naturalism and claims: what ought to be,
can be derived from what is. To be more specific, some existents, i.e.
must-not-be-experiences - non-moral* desires of the non-prevalence of
situations - and prohibitions and punishments, may plausibly be termed
"ought-not-to-be:s" or "should-not-be:s". As prohibitions
derive their "meaning" - their nature as attempts to prevent actions
- from desires, it would seem superfluous to count prohibitions as independent
constituents of injustices, should-not-be:s. Roughly the same applies to
punishments. Desires of avoiding, on the other hand, may well be regarded as
existing, real should-not-be:s - constituents of moral facts. The conclusion
is: there are should-not-be:s and should-be:s, whose existence everyone must
reasonably admit (to the same extent that everyone must reasonably admit
the existence of other beings' experiences in general) = everyone must
reasonably admit true, that some things should (not) be. This leads to
the further conclusion, that a situation may have to be admitted by all to be
both wrong and requisite. Towards the end of the article, a prioritization
system of must-be:s and must-not-be:s, based on degrees of experienced urgency
(=factual importance) or difficulty of ignoring the respective desires, is
proposed. -Suffering is found to be inherently prescriptive (cf. Mackie,
1977), as it cannot be separated from a desire to annihilate it.
*desires not
motivated by moral beliefs
One of the most
widely known sentences in moral philosophy is the thought of David Hume, the
so-called Hume's guillotine: thereof, what is, cannot be derived, what should
(or shouldn't) be. This can be construed to mean, narrowly: from the fact, that
people generally act in a certain way, cannot be deduced, that they act
rightly. This I do not want to deny.
In the following, my aim is to disprove
Hume's guillotine (as far as I know, in a novel way) in its absolute meaning:
from nothing, that is, can be derived, what should (not) be. So, my view
is: it can be inferred from how certain things are, how things should
(not) be. More specifically: some states of affairs, which all "sensorily
healthy" people can perceive ("natural" states of affairs), may
be called should-be:s and should-not-be:s. This I end up with in
discussing, what we mean by "should be" and (particularly)
"should not be" - how we use these expressions.
So, I defend moral naturalism in this
sense: (1) moral sentences, which look like claims are, in fact, claims (not,
e.g., just expressions of the speaker's desires) (2) some such claims are true
(3) moral claims are made true by some opinion-independent traits of the world
(4) the "rightness" and "wrongness" of actions and/or
situations are certain action- and situation-related "natural states of
affairs" = states of affairs, that are often classified as non-moral,
not pure moral-value-beings, moral-value-properties, or relations to such.
These states of affairs are also "natural" = perceivable by senses
common to almost every human being or by introspection (or deducible from such
perceptions), not by a special "moral sense" ("perceptions"
of moral rightness and wrongness vary from one individual to the other, being
"non-natural").
-Naturalism (and naturalness) has several
definitions, but my stance represents in any case objectivism - the
idea, that there is a universal
(opinion-independent) truth about actions' and situations' wrongness,
rightness and requiredness. (I don't talk about realism, as this word
might bring to mind consciousness-independent moral facts, not only opinion-independent
ones*.) As I tie up wrongness and
rightness with experiences, someone may ask, how my position differs from subjectivism
in the broad sense: "moral claims are assertations about the speaker's or
someone else's attitudes towards actions and/or their consequences", but I
promise to make clear, in the end, where the difference from subjectivism lies.
After having shown, that there are moral requirements
"intrinsical to nature", I outline roughly, what they oblige us to -
how we (factually!) should live.
The question, which led me to the views
stated below, is: are there, in spite of everything, correct and incorrect
beliefs about moral rightness (requiredness) and wrongness. (My former position
was the error theory*.) In order to answer this, we must define (1) right and
wrong (2) universal truth. I will ponder on the meanings of "right"
and "wrong" long, before being able to reach my solution. If you find
this pondering uninteresting, you may try jumping right away to my Solution-chapter.
Your chance of understanding it will, though, grow significantly, if you will
first read about my distinction between should-not-be-experience and wrongness-judgment
(History of should not, paragraph 1. - 6.).
Most people probably agree with this much at
least: "Situation X is wrong" can just as well be expressed:
"Situation X should not prevail", "Situation X must
not-prevail". Similarly, "right" means something, that is
(should be) allowed to prevail and "required" something, that must
prevail (like the realization of human rights and actions counted as duties).
But where does "should-be-ness" and its "sisters" abide? Do
they exist objectively or subjectively (in consciousnesses)? If I say: "X
is wrong", do I mean: I want X to not prevail (I experience X, for
instance, as intolerable)? To me it seems apparent, that I mean something more.
In calling X "a moral wrongness" I
mean: it is a fact (not just my feeling), that X should not prevail. As G.E.
Moore already observed, it would be impossible to disagree on moral claims, if
they were only assertations of the speakers' feelings or desires.
Let's suppose, that A says to B:
"Euthanasia is wrong". According to the subjectivist analysis, she
means: "I experience it as intolerable, that someone practise
euthanasia", "I want unconditionally, that euthanasia be not
practised". Now we can assume, that both A and B construe A:s sentence in
this way. (Doesn't "the word means" mean: "The majority of the
users of the word understands the word thus-and-so"?) If so, the sentence
"B thinks A:s wrongness-judgment incorrect" can only mean: B does not
believe, that A experiences the practice of euthanasia (e.g.) intolerable. And
usually - I should say - we don't mean this by "moral
disagreements".
The typical argument in moral disagreements is not, I should think, "Do I
not seem disapproving/detesting?".
The structure of real-life moral argument
insinuates, that our disagreements concern some kind of intrinsical or objective
wrongness, badness (etc.) of actions (their consequences) - not the attitudes
of the moral judges towards actions (consequences).
People, who argue about an action's
wrongness, mean by "moral wrongness", that the action in question should
not, objectively or universally truly, be performed. If the
"shalling-not-be" doesn't factually exist in (for example)
experiencer-independent reality, this proves the assertation "The action
is wrong" incorrect. It doesn't change the meaning of the sentence
into "The action is disapproved/detested by Alice". (Likewise: if it
could be shown, that the world isn't created by an immaterial, conscious being,
the belief in the existence of God would be proven incorrect - "God"
wouldn't cease to mean "world-creator spirit".) If one of the
disputers meant (during the dispute), that an action was universally-truly
wrong, it is still true, that she meant this. And words "mean" - do
they not? - whatever a language user (or majority of language users) means by
them - what she understands them to mean.
To me, at least, it seems apparent: every
person of normal intelligence (who doesn't suffer from value-blindness) means,
by "morally wrong", something universally "shalling-not",
unless philosophical studies have distorted her word sense. Moral arguments are
one piece of evidence for this. Another is the fact, that individuals are
sometimes uncertain about an action's or situation's rightness, plus the fact
that they make efforts to achieve this certainty. (We do not only ask
ourselves, whether a certain action causes something that we detest/dislike -
like suffering - more than the abstaining from this action. We can also ask
ourselves, what are the absolute nonvalues, that should be avoided.)
To sum: I consider the subjectivist
wrongness-definition ("moral claims are only reports about the speaker's
moral sentiments") incorrect. As far as I can see, whoever speaks of
"wrongness" understands herself to be speaking of an objective/universally
true "shalling-not-be", not only of her own relation to the
"wrong" something. (I support Mackie's error theory without the
error, one could say.)
Subjectivism is, of course, not the only
alternative to objectivism. There is (was), for instance, emotivism. I find,
though, that emotivism also can easily be shown as an incorrect position.
Alfred Ayer (Sayer-McCord 1988) proposed,
that sentences of the kind "theft is wrong" are expressions of
feelings, like "Ow!" is an expression of pain, and therefore they
lack truth-value. (The statement "I'm in pain" can be correct or
incorrect, an expression of pain cannot. Here I won't discuss the function of
moral sentences as a means of influencing others' actions, which Ayer also proposed.)
In my opinion, this kind of interpretation is possible only, if we don't pay
enough attention to the meaning of the expression "expression of
emotion".
As far as I can see, "expression of
emotion" means something (a word, a noise, a gesture...) that the emotion
almost forces one to make. According to this (attempt at) definition,
the sentence ""That picture is horrible!" is indeed an
expression of emotion. But it seems to be more than that. The sentence isn't:
"How horrible!", but: "The picture is horrible (horribly
ugly)!". To its structure, the sentence is a statement of ugliness in the
outer world, and is it that only to its structure?
When I see an ugly picture, I feel,
that the ugliness abides in the picture. I don't experience, that the picture
is "out there" and the ugliness "in here", in the
experience of ugliness in my mind. They are both "out there" (not-me)
and inseparable from each other. In our childhood we learn, that beauty
"really" is in the beholder's eye, but our use of language reflects (I
claim) our original experience. It seems natural to think, that by such
sentences we have originally expressed (besides the emotion-expression
function) naïvely realistic beliefs about the ugliness inherent in
objects. If you will: beliefs, that have been caused by projecting our emotions
to the outer world.
My point is: even sentences, that express
"projection-beliefs", are expressions of beliefs. They have a
cognitive content, like "Object X has the perceiver-independent property
'ugliness' ", and therefore they are not only expressions of emotions =
outbursts of emotions. So: if we express, by moral sentences, naïvely realistic
"projection-beliefs" (about moral issues we argue, as if they had a
judge-independent truth), we must consider moral sentences as genuine
belief-expressions, not (merely) expressions of emotions.
As a logical empiricist, Ayer could not have
admitted, that projection-belief expressing sentences are meaningful statements
- they are unverifiable, metaphysical sentences. But this doesn't justify the
conclusion, that expressing emootions is their (only) function. If moral
sentences express the value-projections of the speaker, even a logical
empiricist must recognize them at least as expressions of pseudo-beliefs.
Keeping my emotion-expression definition in
mind: the sentence "That picture is horrible!" is undisputably (among
other things) an expression of emotion. On the other hand, in the sentence
"She thought it horrible", the word "horrible" cannot be an
emotion-expression - it is a statement about an other person's emotion (and
projection-belief, maybe). Similarly, if I ask myself: "Would it be wrong
of me to participate in research about bacteriological weapons?", the word
"wrong" cannot be an expression of emotion. Or what would it mean to
say: "Would it be "Ow!" of me to participate in
research...?". An what could emotivist argumentation for the wrongness of
the research be - argumentation in favour of "Ow!"? If a sentence
asks somehing, it isn't an expression of feeling - when we ask, we are
uncertain of the badness, wrongness etc.
of an action. If a question, not an expression - if an expression, not a
question.
If we suppose, that the meaning of the word
"wrong" is in a broad sense "emotive", emotion-pertaining,
my question could be given the meaning: would research on bacteriological
weapons have consequences, that I would find, e.g., horrible. And this would,
of course, not be an emotivist, but a subjectivist interpretation. According to
it, "wrong" refers to "what I find horrible".
There are similar problems in prescriptivism
- the view "Moral 'claims' and terms are recommendations meant as
universally applicable". Again, my "claim" of the requiredness
of action X might only be a prescription that I mean as universal, but what
does the (often asked) question, whether an action is required, mean?
Perhaps, whether an action is worth being recommended? But if so, the
term "required" refers to something worth recommending
(we don't merely use it to recommend).
-Perhaps we do mean this by
"right"/"required", also in assertations? Perhaps moral
arguments are attempts at showing actions worth recommending and prohibiting
(whatever we mean by "worth")?
As a further challenge to non-cognitivist
positions - positions that moral sentences don't express beliefs (but are
language games) - one might ask: can a speaker be wrong in her impression, that
she has a belief concerning the outer world? And does unverifiability of a
"belief" make it not a belief, but a motive for a language game (an
outbursting emotion, a desire to influence actions) or a reaction to a language
game move (sympathy, a desire to obey)?
Therefore I claim: in talking about moral
wrongness or rightness we do refer to something, and not only our own emotions
or desires. For my own part I know for certain: when I think about the
wrongness of an action, a certain image springs to my mind: an image of a world-pervading,
human being-independent non-allowing of the action - not only of the
detestable traits of the action (its consequences) plus my own detestation.
Even if you don't agree with my idea of the
meaning of "wrong", I ask you to notice: in this paper I use
the expression "moral wrongness" in the meaning "universally
true shalling-not-be". Or, more specifically: categorical
universally-true shalling-not-be. According to Kant's terminology,
"hypothetical imperatives" are often universally true, but they are
not considered moral assertations.
An example of a hypothetical imperative
could be: "Always boil eggs for 12 minutes, if you want to eat hard-boiled
eggs". This can be considered another way to say: the boiling of eggs for
12 minutes is the sufficient condition of the eggs coagulating thoroughly. This
may be a universally-true fact, but no universally-true duty concerning
the boiling tiome follows from it. The imperative is morally meaningless.
An example of categorical imperative could
be: "Don't fish the seas empty, for even your grandchildren will want a
well-balanced diet". This imperative is motivated by a desire, but
it is categorical - unconditional (maybe in a non-Kantian way) - in that the
listeners are not left any alternative concerning their actions. So, my
intention is to discuss, whether there is any (in this sense) categorical,
universally-true shalling-not-be.
The history of
"should not"
So far I have
said: an action or a situation is called "morally wrong", when it is
believed a universal truth, that the action or situation should not be.
What does it mean, then, that something "should not" be?
I have often noticed, that it becomes easier
to understand the meanings of expressions, if I ask myself: what can have made
the expression useful. In this case: what kind of thing, that someone has come
across, could have made her say (or exclaim, or groan): this should not be? (I
mean generally, not only in moral contexts.)
One obvious answer is: the experience, that
something is intolerable. For example, losing a thing, without which we
"cannot imagine ourselves to live" (our spouse, our extremities, the
respect of society). Or "intolerable" suffering, like an intense
pain. If I would, while in pain, care about self-expression, I might well
express my experience like this: this shouldn't be, this must end.
Below, I call this kind of experiences should-not-be experiences. These
must be distinguished from injustice-judgments (should-not-be- judgments,
should-not-be opinions).
A should-not-be experience is morally
neutral - it isn't (necessarily) conjoined with the view of the universal truth
of the "shalling-not-be". A should-not-be experience is not a view
at all, but a desire of something terrible ending. Injustice-judgments
are often accompanied by ending-desires, but an ending-desire = should-not-be
experience and an injustice-judgment are (in my notion system) different
things.
There can be an ending-desire without
injustice-judgment - I can want my pain to end, but believe that it isn't
wrong, because no human being has caused it/because a good and just God allows
it to prevail. There can be injustice-judgment without ending-desire - I can
believe that suffering is always wrong, but get vengeful satisfaction from the
suffering of my malefactor.
Someone may answer this by: "It is true,
that we often "consider wrong" the satisfying of our revenge-desire.
But you haven't shown, that our "injustice-judgment" is a genuine
belief, not another desire. After all, we do often have desires, which conflict
with each other!". This I admit.
If the individual struggles with her
revenge-desire, then the counterforce of the revenge-desire is even necessarily
another desire. What else could motivate to struggle (or any action) than some
desire, or will (chosen action plan) caused by a desire? I claim, though, that
the other desire in question is motivated by the moral belief (so there is a
moral belief distinguishable from the desirer). Desires to avoid injustice are
not just desires among others. If I consider an action (e.g. sexual infidelity)
wrong, I attempt to avoid it unconditionally - I strive to avoid the action
even, if I have a "compellingly" strong desire to it.
So, my "moral desire" is for me an
overriding motive among desires, or: I am committed to always
obey it. Moral views (of the kind "One must act thus") are not only
desires, whose superior intensity makes the individual always act upon them,
but the moral agent has decided to act, unconditionally, according to
them - as far as I can see, because she believes, that their consequences
"should be" more forcefully than (other) things she desires. (More accurately, I think: when a moral agent
believes, that a certain action is wrong, she decides to abstain from
it, because she, as a child, has made the more general decision to always
act rightly - because she wanted to be loved by her parents/God...)
So I claim - to those, whose own
introspection or the dispute-impossibility argument (by Moore) doesn't convince
of this: "injustice-judgments" are genuine beliefs. Not desires, but
partial motives of moral commitments. The distinction between
injustice-judgments and should-not-be experiences = avoiding-desires is
justified. (Even if all moral judgments were desires, I suppose everyone
admits, that all desires are not moral judgments?)
So, the sentence "X shouldn't be"
can (in non-moral use) express the experience of the intolerability of X and
desire that X end, the experience of the "necessity" of X ending*.
(These are hardly separable from each other. An experience of intolerability
can hardly prevail without a desire of ending, or a compelling desire of ending
without the experience of intolerability.)
The expression "should not" has
another common non-moral meaning (group of meanings) as well. "You should
not do X, Matthew" is a prohibition - an attempt to stop Matthew doing X.
The passive mode of a prohibition - "X
should not be done" - is used when meaning, that someone or something (the
parents, the law/ruler/parliament, the rules of a game...) has prohibited
doing X (and imposed a punishment for it). Even this use might have its roots
in the experience of intolerability. If a person, who holds a power position,
says, that one should not do X, meaning "I don't tolerate X being
done", her subjects know that their lives will become difficult, if they
disregard this experience of intolerability.
-I admit it possible, that the prohibition
is the older meaning of "should not". In any case, the experience of
intolerability and desire of avoiding are psychologically primary - there
wouldn't be prohibitions without them.
When adopting a prohibition as a guiding
principle, even the subject (employee, child...) thinks: I should not do
X, meaning: Don't do X!, that is, she has a plan, an intention to
avoid doing X.
So far I have spoken of (according to one
way of counting) three meaning groups of "should not be (done)",
besides its use as a prohibition: "I want unconditionally, that it isn't
done"/"I find it intolerable"; "It is prohibited/punished";
I intend not to do it". All of these include some kind of turning away
from the injust thing (avoiding or ending, or a desire to do so).
Does "shalling-not" have a fourth,
strictly moral meaning? A quite distinctive meaning, not just an objectified
(de-humanized) away-turning (as-if desire to demolish, desire of avoiding or
prohibition)?
My sense of language says: even moral speech
of "shalling-not-be" expresses an away-turning. The expression
"it is wrong" brings to my mind an image, where the world itself
looks sternly at the unjust action, struggles to vomit the action/agent out of
its insides and only achieves peace, when it is gone. (The world as if
struggles and as if is appeased - I don't really consider the world an
experiencing being.)
As I don't have actual perceptions of the
world's vomiting attempts, I dare to conclude, that I am objectifying a human
away-turning.
But can I really claim that I mean,
by "shalling-not-be", something that the world strives to vomit out?
If I would see the Earth open and a lava jet belch a man into outer space,
would I nod in a convinced fashion: he has not lived justly? Hardly, I
should say. Even if I perceived something, that I considered a certain sign of
the Earth's disgust and intention to spew out the unlucky man, I would think:
even the Earth is only one experiencing subject. Even the Earth's disgust is
subjective - existing only in the Earth's consciousness - not a sign of the
detestability inherent in the man himself.
Closer to a perception of objective
shalling-not-be would come the instance, that the Earth would spew out the man of
its intention, but without feeling (still assuming, that I can e.g.
telepathically perceive the Earth's mind contents). Would I be prepared to
construe as an injustice this completely motive-less out-spewing? No - I would
consider it morally indifferent (just like an involuntary physical event).
I am ready to admit something a moral
injustice only, if I perceive the Earth spewing out the man because it can
see, that he has acted unjustly (I remind you: in my image the world or the
Earth looks stern). And if so, the injustice isn't constituted by the Earth's
emotions, but by something else, that the Earth knows about.
It seems, after all, that by
"injustice"/"shalling-not-be" I don't mean the
Earth's/world's relation to things. Why did I, then, take it up? Because my
image of "shalling-not" is my only clue to what I mean by "moral
shalling-not-be". It seems that I mean by "moral shalling-not"
something, that the world struggles to spew out (I cannot mean by expressions
something that never enters my mind), but only as far as I don't analyze it too
much.
In principle I mean an objective
shalling-not-be, but I can only imagine a shalling-not-be by imagining mind
contents: ending-attempts and -desires. (By transferring them into the
lifeless world - outside the minds of people, animals and gods - I try to make
them non-mind-contents, non-subjective. It still seems like moral shalling-not-be
is only (partially) objectified human shalling-not-be. This is the case at
least, if my idea of injustice resembles that of most people. But maybe it
doesn't?
I dare to claim, that all images of
injustice = shalling-not-be contain a direction: "This (injustice)
away!". The image of injustice always contains an exiting-movement of the
wrong (the intention of removal, the desire of removal...). Do we, then, mean
this removal-motion, when we talk about shalling-not-be? Could some kind of
away-movement be the objective (not objectified) shalling-not-be, that we are
looking for? In other words: are there exiting-movements, that we would
recognize as constituting objective shalling-not-be:s?
I begin to discuss this by asking, what
kinds of "exiting-movements" we are capable of observing. During my
life I have observed (1) actual events of ending or moving away, that
is: my sense perceptions of something exiting from somewhere. As actual
exiting-events I also count images (including memories, hallucinations
and dream images) of something exiting something (unless these images are
conjoined with removing-desires or, in general, exiting-movements of other
classes) (2a) my attempts or will exertions to remove something
(motivated by desire of removal) (2b) my impressions of removing-attempts in
others (other people flee from and extinguish fires or remove splinters
from their fingers, like I do - I believe that others also move of their own
intention and intention-motivating desires (3a) my desires of removing something
(often motivated by an experience of intolerability) (3b) impressions of
removing-desires in other people and animals (not unlike (2b)) or
disgust/suffering, annexed to the desire of avoiding or demolishing the
disgusting/painful (4) plans, decisions l. intentions (in the future, in
certain situations) to attempt removing something (5) prohibitions
(motivated by a desire to demolish or prevent from starting) (6) the punishability
of actions.
It seems like we wouldn't mean any of these
things by "moral shalling-not-be".
(1) When something
actually ends, the ending only happens, not should not happen.
(More accurately: ending in itself isn't shalling-to-end. Construed in this
way, I do accept Hume's guillotine.) Factual endings we find morally
indifferent, not constituting moral injustice.
(2), (4), (5), (6) When we come across an
attempt of removing something, we ask ourselves, why the removed or
attempted-to-remove "should not be". The same applies to
removing-plans, prohibitions and punishments. We find none of these
constitutive of moral shalling-not-be.
(3) A desire to remove is, I admit, a motive
to remove - we don't ask, why the desired-to-end must be ended (particularly
not, if we are acquainted with the intolerability-experience annexed to it) -
but not an objective motive, if "objective" means
"experience-independently existing", "non-experiential". An
objective motive would be something, that would be just like a desire, but not-experienced.
And such things we cannot perceive. (Neither do we have impressions of such
things - we are not inclined to interpret the movements of animals, plants or
lifeless matter as motivated by non-experiential desires.)
My point is: the only "exiting-movements",
that we are capable of observing, are actual exitings and subjective making-to-exit
inclinations (also prohibitions expressed by someone, that are motivated by
a making-to-exit inclination). If we believe the shalling-not-be to be another kind
of exiting-movement than these - more objective than desires and intentions,
more normative than actual exitings - then we do not have perceptions of such
things (or only exceptional individuals have). Therefore I dare to claim: the
view of "objective shalling-not-be:s" is an objectification of
desires, intentions or prohibitions.
This can be stated more concisely: the wrong
is something, which objectively has to not be. What does "has
to" mean, if it doesn't express a desire (non-objective) or an injunction
(morally irrelevant)?
Above I indicated one possible answer:
perhaps we do innately experience the ending-desire (or the terribleness, which
causes the ending-desire) to abide in the outer world. (This would mean, that
the idea of "objective injustice" would after all stem from our
experiences. When growing up, we would only learn, that experiences are not to
be trusted.) Perhaps we don't actively objectify our
experience-contents, but learn to subjectify them, when coming across
world views, that differ from our own. In the case of injustice-experiences we
only, of some reason, do not learn this subjectification (in spite of running
to opposite views). Perhaps this is because our moral educators emphatically
stress the correctness of their own (in)justice-views? Perhaps the nature of
moral injuctions as enablers of a tolerable life (and a life tout court)
causes people to think it more important to propagate their justice- and injustice-views than their views
of style? (Even those are propagated with remarkable passion, I admit. And do
we believe in our hearts, that there isn't one single truth about style
questions?)
Could this kind of projectivism be the
correct explanation of our experience of the objectivity of injustice?
As a child, I may well have believed, that
the terribleness, that I observe, is located in the outer world. But
terribleness isn't shalling-not-be. A desire to demolish could be called
shalling-not-be ("that should not be" is an expression of the desire
to demolish). But have I at some point believed, that the desire to demolish
the wrong is located in the outer world (not God, either*)? This I cannot
remember, although I remember a good part of my childhood since the age of
three.
But perhaps I have "projected" only
some of the traits of my demolishing-desire onto the outer world? Perhaps I
only see, in the outer world, a forceful intention to demolish the
wrong, a movement towards demolishing the wrong? (What else do we, after
all, observe in our desires? Well - perhaps the suffering, that motivates
them.)
If the "projected" striving-to-end
is the only meaning of "morally wrong", I must interpret
"morally wrong" in this way even in my adulthood - in so far as
injustices exist, I must see an ending-attempt in the outer world. This is not
a problem, since I just admitted, that my image of shalling-not-be is an image
of a forceful struggle to vomit out the wrong.
In spite of this, I offer another,
alternative or complementary, explanation: ideas of desire-less shalling-not-be:s
and shalling-be:s are generated by a linguistic confusion.
Beside moral, general rights and
wrongs, we talk about rightness and wrongness relative to achieving a
certain goal - a right or wrong solution, mode of use etc. (the
"hypothetical imperative" of Kant). If I am going to a concert at the
stadium, the "right" route is one, that brings me to the stadium,
preferably before the start of the concert. More pertinently in this context: a
mother may teach her children: "One should do so and so" ("Only
this is right") when meaning "Those who act differently, the society
despises and ostracizes". Since almost everyone wants to avoid social
seclusion, it seems unnecessary to specify: "...if you want to
avoid social seclusion". Perhaps the idea of a generally applicable right
and wrong has been caused by this kind of teachings?
Let's consider, how a child learns the
meaning of "should not do". The child's first contact with the
expressions "should not" and "should" is certainly an
injunction of the parents - after all, the earliest education is based on those
- the "understanding" of which means, roughly, that the child obeys
the injunction. (If disobedience is followed by a punishment, that the child
wants to avoid, then the injunction is, for her, not a hypothetical imperative
- she doesn't deliberate every time, whether to choose the punishment or the
not-punishment.)
The child learns to respond to injunctions
by acting accordingly to them - since all injunctions
are always in
force, by committing herself to action plans in line with them. The
"meaning" of the injunction is, for her, essentially her intention
to do what is told (surely also the thought content "the speaker wants
me to act thus and so"). The injuction is an incentive to form a certain
action plan, provided that the child believes herself to be punished for
disobedience. (The willingness of the child to adopt the action plan is
undoubtedly strengthened by the parents' convincing the child of the ugliness
or painful consequences (for someone) of an action, or convincing her, that
obedience of an injunction is God's will or otherwise admirable.)
As the child now knows the
"meanings" of injunctions, and she is taught, how one should act in
life - without mention of the alternative of common contempt and social
isolation - she "understands" the teachings: "Something
expects of me an unconditional commitment to a certain course of action".
And apparently this is not only the desire of her parents, as (1) the parents
obey the same rules, whether they want to or not (2) the same rules are
recognized everywhere in society.
The child forms an image of an action
instruction, that (itself) expects to be obeyed - a demand, that exists
independently of human demanders and their desires. The
"objectifying" of the demand is only the denying of subjects.
Additionally: when striving to adopt (internalize) the demand of abstaining
from an action, the child must imagine (at least) that the forbidden action is
moving away from its object, and thus ending. Little by little the child will
probably learn to think about the action only as annexed to a movement
away.
Perhaps this engenders the image of an
action-demolishing intention in the outer world? Or the action-demolishing
intention inherent in the action itself? (I am not saying, that the idea of a
subject-less demand would suffice as a motive for a small child to obey the
demand. I am only talking about the meaning of "objective
shalling-not". Above I proposed some possible motives. -For an adult, the
belief in "objective shalling-not" may well suffice as a triggering
motive of not-doing, since she already has the "will", the intention,
to always act rightly.)
The child connects injunctions with
unconditional expectations, because (I dare to generalize) her parents have
presented their injunctions persistently, only easing off when the child obeys
them - but she denies, that expectors be the sources of the guiding
principles - after all, expectors, who announce themselves as sources, are
nowhere to be seen. ("Because I say so" is surely, more often than
not, a last resource and expression of fatigue.)
So, I think: with moral
"injustice" and "requiredness" we are only referring to the
existence of a universal, always applicable acting instruction, which requires
obedience of itself. (Or something, whereof the lifeless world requires
obedience.) A user of language can, as observed, mean by her expressions only
such a thing, that is in her mind at least part of the time.
This definition may seem unsatisfactory.
Even if there are, somewhere, as-if-demands independent of demanders, what
about it? Why should we act according to them? Demands are moral only when
motivated!
It seems, that we have in our minds, after
all, a not-yet-mentioned criterion of moral prohibitedness and requiredness:
grounds. And what do we, in this context, mean by "grounds"? In which
way does the objective non-prevailing demand follow from its reason?
Logically, causally?
Must the truth of a
"should-not-be"-demand follow logically from its reason - or must the
shalling-not-be follow from it logically (what would the
"truth" of a demand be)? And what is a truth of a
shalling-not-be?
According to the correspondence theory of
truth, a sentence is correct (true) only if it corresponds with a state of
affairs, that prevails - existents (and their relations), that exist. According
to this, a shalling-not-be can only be true, if some kind of a shalling-be
exists - maybe a demand, that is "objective" = given by a non-human,
mindless being (not tied to a human desire). Now: the truth of shalling-not-be
- the existence of a should-not-be demand - can only be inferred from something
(a feature of the "unjust" action/situation?), that contains a
"should-not-be" demand. (Logical proofs are tautologies - e.g.
Wittgenstein 1997.)
Philippa Foot (1958/2010) has proposed, that
several non-value-natured components could together form a value, but
for my part I cannot see, what we would consider components of a demand,
if not a desire, its expression and and the intention of affecting others'
actions.) But is this the kind of grounds, that we want for
non-prevailing-demands? Do we, by "grounds for the prohibition of an
action", mean the proof, that the prohibition exists? I believe:
even in the case, that I would know the (perhaps objective) demand to
exist, I would want the demand to have grounds, before I would recognize it as
a moral demand. Do we not rather mean, by "grounds", a proof thereof,
that the action should be or would be good to prohibit?
I claim: in everyday moral reasonings we
accept as grounds for prohibiting an action only, that the action leads to a bad
consequence - something, that we experience aas terrible, like another person's
pain or the ugliness of the world. If an action causes - or is intended to
cause - more bad than good, most people admit without further questions, that
the action should not be exerted.
Badness is not a logical reason of
shalling-not-be, nor goodness the logical reason for requiredness (at least in
an obvious way), but it is a commonly accepted reason. (This is obviously
analogical with the connection, that pleasure and pain have with desires. Since
I find that a mango tastes better than a lemon, I want to eat a
mango rather than a lemon.) We consider the bad consequences of an action to be
grounds for avoiding the action.
Maybe we would, then, recognize an action as
morally wrong provided, that the non-experiential terribleness of a
situation consequent to the action would lead to the non-experiential
desire (or stopping-attempt) of the world, that the situation cease to
prevail - similarly, like the experiences of intolerability lead to the
ending-desires of situations? This would be a causal consequence, not a logical
one - at least on the face of it.
Would we recognize this as the groundedness
(motivatedness), that we are looking for? Or even something less - the degree
of non-experiential terribleness of an action's consequence, which would make
it deserve our ending-desire more than the consequences of alternative actions?
Or a subjective terribleness (painfulness?), that the world perceives correctly
(the perception content being "objective" = like its object), and
which leads to the non-experiential ending-"desire" of the world?
I am tempted to ask, why we want grounds for
the objective shalling-not-be:s of situations in the first place. Perhaps in
order to be convinced, that they are shalling-not-be:s? But the truth of
a shalling-not-be claim doesn't need other proofs than the existence of the
shalling-not-be (for instance, desire that a situation not prevail).
Could objective injustice in the here
described sense - possibly non-experiential terribleness, that possibly leads
to non-experiential desires - exist? Many a materialist would perhaps defend
the stance: for every possible experience-content it is logically possible to
exist also as non-experiential. Equally well, that one can imagine a
non-experiential dimensional shape (of a physical body), one can imagine a
non-experiential desire (or an "experience" of an ending-necessity or
terribleness). Or equally badly: even a non-experiential shape cannot be
imagined. Like Berkeley remarked, every imagined "non-experiential
tree" is an image of a tree, an experience.
On the other hand: even though a
non-experiential (non-phenomenal) tree or other material body cannot be
imagined, it can be thought of. One can think of an existent, which is
characterized by (1) the shape and colour of a seen tree (2) non-phenomenality
in itself (the existent may cause sensations, but is not one). Non-experiential
desires and terriblenesses are thinkable in the same sense. But on the other
(third?) hand: even if non-experiential desires or terriblenesses do exist,
they are of no help in real-life moral dilemmas - we cannot observe them or
infer their presence. The world deserves better!
The solution
The world may not
contain observable entities or relations, that correspond exactly with our
images of shalling-not-be - demands or desires, that are motivated by
non-experiential terribleness, and/or are in themselves non-experiential
(assuming, that our images are like this). If they did exist, I am sure
children would learn them at school beside the multiplication tables. But
perhaps there is something in the world, that we would be ready to call
objective or factual shalling-not-be?
As I have said, objective = (1) experience-independent, non-experiential
shalling-not-be:s cannot be observed by us. But why should injustice be
independent of experiences? Isn't it enough, that it is a fact, that no one can
reasonably deny - a view-independent fact?
After all, the word "objective" is
often used in this sense as well - of things, whose (2)
observability/admittedness doesn't depend on the differences of
("normal") subjects.
Experiences are subjective according to
definition (1), but they are admitted to exist by almost everyone - even the
experiences of others. At least: if other people's and animals' experiences
don't exist, most part of morals becomes unneeded (all prohibitions, except
those of (to God) despicable actions, like sex with a facade of an animal or
the perpetrator's mother?).
The majority of moral decisions are in any
case made based on the uncertain belief, that there are experiences of
suffering, pleasure and contentedness, and those not only in the
decision-maker's consciousness. Why could we not ground the moral norms themselves
on the knowledge/faith concerning experiences? (I speak hypothetically, as I
haven't yet shown, that this would be motivated.)
I suggest, that we content ourselves with
the demand: moral shalling-not-be:s must be facts admitted by everyone
(admitted when making practical decisions, if not when philosophizing).
Now: what does "fact" or
"truth" mean? I still vouch for the correspondence theory: a sentence
or a belief can be correct (true) or incorrect (false) only by corresponding or conflicting with what is. That a state of
affairs should not prevail, can be true (or false) only if there is
something (at least imaginable), that we would admit as shalling-not-prevail.
So we must ask: is there in "wrong" situations something, that
we would be ready to call the "shalling-not" itself?
Hume's guillotine, or rather: the strong
interpretation of the guillotine, denies this. In "A Treatise of Human
Nature" [1740] Hume opposed the ethicists, that he knew, in some way like
this (a translation from Finnish - sorry): "I want to add to these
conclusions an observation, that might be to some degree important. In every
moral system, which I have hitherto come across, I have observed that the
writer begins by usual inferences, where the subject and the predicate are
combined with the words is and is not - by postulating the
existence of God or making observations of human affairs - when suddenly I
notice, that I cannot find any proposition, whose parts are not connected by
the words should or should not. The transition is subtle, but
extremely important. Since this should or should not expresses
some new relation or proposition, it should necessarily be noticed and
explained. Explained should also be the circumstance, that seems
incomprehensible: how this new relation can be inferred from other relations of
quite a different nature. But as writers generally don't take this precaution,
I take it as my right to recommend it to readers. I am sure, that this small
attention disproves all customary moral systems and proves, that the
distinction of vice and virtue is not founded merely on the relations of
objects, nor is perceived by reason."
If the passage is studied by itself, Hume
may seem to speak moderately - he says only, that it seems incomprehensible,
how a relation can be inferred from relations of another nature; that the
distinction between vice and virtue is not perceived by reason (not,
that it isn't perceivable by reason in theory).
Even the passage "disproves all
customary moral systems and proves, that the distinction between vice and
virtue is not founded merely on the relations of objects" could be
interpreted weakly: in the moral texts, that Hume knows, the ethicists have
not ended up with their "virtue"- and "vice"-labels
solely on the basis of the relations of objects, that they mention; the
reasonings in favour of the moral systems, that he knows, are disproved
as insufficient.
On the other hand, the text that precedes
the "guillotine-passage" seems to show, that the right interpretation
is stronger than this: goodness/badness/shalling-do cannot even in theory be
inferred logically from the relations of objects, or from what is. Hume
asks, namely, whether the vice factually inheres in objects - for instance,
whether some of the things pertaining to a murder is the vice (vice being, vice
relation) itself - and answers negatively. Therefore I believe, that the
common, strong interpretation - "values cannot be derived from facts"
- is justified (represents Hume's view correctly).
Unanswered is still the question, what Hume
or later guillotinists recognize as "objects", "existing"
or "facts". Moore's talk about "natural properties" or
"describing terms" doesn't make this clearer. Like Philippa Foot
observes, "good" is a describing term in the common sense of
"describing".
In "Treatise" Hume gives a clue to
this: he says, that we perceive the vicefulness of an action by our own
disapproval: "Here we have a fact, but it is an object of
sentiment, not reason; inherent not in the object, but in ourselves". Hume
seems to think, that nothing but the moral judge's sentiment can
constitute vice or injustice. If I am right, it doesn't make any difference,
whether he would in principle have recognized (e.g.) the suffering of a victim
of injustice as an "object". The guillotine can be made more
explicit: badness, vice etc. cannot be inferred logically from anything else
that exists than the moral judge's sentiment (which doesn't make the action
bad in a generally applicable, factual way?).
Additionally Hume seems to think, that the
moral judge doesn't infer badness even from her own sentiment ("not
an object of reason"), whatever this means* (note in end of this chapter)
- she just feels it. If I am right, we are justified in ascribing to Hume a
still more general claim: "Goodness/badness/shalling-be cannot be inferred
logically from anything, that exists in any way (in or out of
consciousnesses)".
My aim here is to discuss the truth of the
guillotine in a narrower sense than this: moral norms (shalling-be,
shalling-not-be) cannot be inferred logically from any existing things.
Interpreted in this way, the necessary truth-condition of the guillotine is:
the prevalence of the state of affairs X is never the shalling-be of a
state of affairs (X, Y or Z). If the existence of an entity would be
an(other) entity's shalling-be, the latter could unproblematically be
"inferred" from the earlier. If Hume wanted to deny this possibility
- held impossible the inferring of shalling-be from what is, because being
cannot be equated with shalling-be, we could counter him by adapting Foot:
the claim, that being is never shalling-be, is obviously true only if we have
decided in advance, that we would call nothing existing
"shalling-be".
Also worth investigating is, what we mean by
"shalling-be". If we don't recognize anything imaginable as
"shalling-be", the guillotine is not true but meaningless. But
perhaps Hume gave it a meaning in his mind?
We know, that by "vice" Hume meant
"disapproved-of". Let's suppose, that he reasoned: similarly, like
the word "good" only expresses the experience of pleasure of the
speaker, the expression "shall be/do" is only an expression of a
desire or a demand. (For my part, I would perhaps not call either an expression
of sentiment, but let's suppose that Hume would - I see no other way to find a
meaning for the guillotine.) A demand doesn't express a fact, so it cannot be a
result of reasoning; the speaker ends up with her desire by inner inclination,
not by reasoning. Ergo: "shalling-be-beliefs" viz. desires or demands
cannot be inferred from being-beliefs. (Or: only that kind of reasoning, that
seems to show, that a certain action leads to a situation, that the moral judge
desires, can make her desire the action l. end up with a "the action must
be performed-belief". Absolute values cannot be inferred logically
from being-beliefs.)
In this way, the sentence "no
shalling-be from being" would acquire the sense: subjective desires or
human demands cannot be inferred from beliefs concerning what is.
The sentence "no shalling-be from
being" is meaningful and true on these conditions: in moral
contexts, we use, and are justified to use, the expression "should
be" only as an expression of a desire or a demand. We are not to call anything
existing "shalling-be" - otherwise we would have to infer shalling-be
from being. The expression "should be" is not allowed to be even a
statement of the desire of the speaker. It can only be an almost-groan
engendered by a compelling desire - or a demand, an attempt to make others
fulfil the speaker's desire. -I admit, that Hume didn't explicitly define
"shalling-be" in this way.
I rephrase my earlier question: is there
(does there exist) something, that we would be ready and justified to
call shalling-be or shalling-not-be? My answer is affirmative.
If we ignore the hard-to-understand moral
expressions and the hypothetical imperative, there remains (as far as I can
see) five observable things, that we express with the word trio "should
not be/do": (1) the prohibition (2) the prohibitedness (by someone/thing
else than the speaker) (3) the punishability of an action (4) the should-not-be
experience (an experience of intolerability conjoined with the desire that the
intolerable end) (5) the will, that the action is not performed = a somewhat
stable intention to refrain from an action and/or try to stop others from
performing an action/causing certain consequences. Therefore I think: a
prohibition, a punishment, an ending-desire (also of others than the speaker)
and intention to refrain or to stop - each directed at an action or a situation
- can well be called shalling-not-be of an action or a situation.
A possible counter is, that in normal use of
language we never talk about the state of affairs (or being) of
"shalling-not-be". In normal use of language it is only said, that
something should not be (done) - and this is only an expression of the speaker's
desire (not a statement, that the speaker's desire exists, either).
I defend myself: we don't use the
expression "should not be (done)" only as an expression of our
desires. (1) Punishments or prohibitedness by law, whose existence the
expression "should not be done" refers to, are clearly not desires of
the speaker. (2) In moral language, "should not be" refers specifically
to a "shalling-not-be" outside the speaker - an objective demand (or
the like), that the speaker believes in. If the parties of moral arguments
would talk (understand themselves to talk) only of their own wishes, moral arguments
would be impossible. Our use
of language
contains, after all, an idea of a state of affairs or being of
shalling-not - an existing (as if-)demand, that constitutes the state of
affairs "X should not be". Therefore I consider it justified to (at
least) ask, if there is any shalling-not-be.
If something existing corresponds with our
ideas/images of what "shalling-not-be" means, we are justified in
claiming, that there is a shalling-not-be (injustice). So what do we
understand that "shall-not-be" means or expresses? I answer: 1. A
prohibition 2. prohibitedness 3. punishability 4. a should-not-be experience
and (maybe) 5. the will/intention to avoid an action. These are namely the only
meanings, in which we use the expression "should not be". Or,
more accurately: they are the only original, non-objectified meanings,
and the objectified (moral) meaning necessarily resembles them. So I think: a
prohibition, a punishment and a should-not-be-experience can be held as existing
shalling-not-be:s. (Further on, I make yet another attempt to show, that
this isn't autocratic use of language.) A state of affairs or an action,
towards which a prohibition, a punishment or a should-not-be experience is
directed, has thus to be considered as factually shalling-not be. A
claim is true, if it represents correctly something existing.
Let's now consider the different candidates
closer. First: does the expression "should not do" intended as a
prohibition refer to factual shalling-not-do:s? A prohibition is an attempt
to stop others doing something. The expression "should not" intended
as a prohibition is only a pawn in a language game - it doesn't refer to
anything existing. So, the prohibiting "should not" lacks truth-value
(wherefore it cannot be true).
The expression "should not do" is
also used in a second order meaning - meaning, that something is prohibited
- by a parent, a ruler, the law, God - that is, there is a prohibition (or the
prohibition has at some time been proposed and is meant to be still in force). Prohibiting
sentences don't refer to anything existing, but sentences that state the
existence of prohibitions do - the prohibitions (and punishments) themselves
could be called existing shalling-not-be:s. But does this make
prohibitedness a moral fact? Does it create an indisputable duty to avoid
performing an action or causing a consequence?
Above I said, that we only consider
prohibitions and demands moral, if they are motivated. It is easy to see, that
a prohibition in itself does not contain its reason.
Another counterargument for a prohibition's
nature as moral fact is this. A prohibition is only an attempt to stop others
performing an action. I mean: the "meaning"- language-game-pawn
-ness, of a prohibition is caused by the attempt to control. (Could the
reciting of the song "Don't speak" be considered a prohibition?)
An attempt to influence cannot exist without
the desire to influence - or the will (intention) to influence, but even the
will is caused by a desire (e.g. the will to go to work five days a week by a
desire to gain one's livelihood).
As there is no prohibition without a desire
(at least a has-been desire, in the case of recorded prohibitions), is it
needful to bring other shalling-not-be:s beside desires?
I suggest, that we deny the access among
moral facts from prohibitions and prohibitedness. But what should we say about
punishments? Must the punishability of an action be considered as its factual
shalling-not-be? In a certain sense it is undisputably so. We say
"it should not be done" meaning (sometimes), that "it" is
punished. Could we say of a punishment the same as of a prohibition: we
consider it moral only if it is motivated? No - the punishment is a
reason for avoiding the action!
One can say so. A punishment is, though, a
reason for avoiding an action (or reason to avoid getting caught...) only for
an agent, who wants to avoid the punishment. No desire, no
avoiding-reason.
There is another reason to ask, whether the
punishment in itself is a "factual shalling-not-do". We use the
expressions "should not be" and "must refrain" in contexts,
where something directs "compellingly" towards avoiding the
action in question. The punishment would not direct people to avoid the action,
if it weren't for the punishment-avoiding desire of the potential agents. Even
here, the desire is the ultimate creator of "shalling-not-do". Why
engage in double bookkeeping?
Fourth: could the refraining-wills of
individuals - refraining-intentions that are "in force" as a result
of decisions - be considered as shalling-not-do:s? (If intentions are always
caused by desires, clearly not as independently existing
shalling-not-do:s.)
The sentence "I should not do so and
so" is a prohibition directed at the speaker herself. "I should
not..." is an attempt to strengthen the commitment to an action-plan and
thus an expression of intention. But would we call our
refraining-intention an existing shalling-not-do?
Do we perhaps feel, that actions are
shalling-not-be only through (consequence-avoiding)desires or through their
moral injustice (things, that lead to our refraining-intention)? Are
intentions only attempts to avoid, what is from the start shalling-not-be? I
feel tempted to say: refraining-intentions themselves are at least not
motivated shalling-not-be:s, contain their own reasons. Desires and
injustice-views are their reasons.
On the other hand, one might think: our
refraining-decision makes us also desire avoiding an action (even though
we would in the beginning only want to avoid the consequences). We want,
because we will (intend). Therefore: insofar as desires are undisputable
shalling-not-be:s, wills/intentions are never morally insignificant.
How is it, then: can the should-not-be-experience
(experience of intolerability and desire of ending the intolerable thing) be
considered a factual and duty-creating should-not-be? My answer is
affirmative. But before I motivate this, you may wish to know, how the idea of
a should-not-be experience constituting injustice differs from subjectivism.
According to (a certain kind of)
subjectivism, one who speaks of an action's justice or injustice only means,
that she has a positive or negative attitude towards the action. The justice is
thus speaker-dependent, not universal. I for my part claim, that by our speech
of moral "justice" and "injustice" we mean universal facts,
but we are justified to admit (of all the things we can observe) as
universally true only "should not be", "is allowed to be"
and "must be"-experiences (as universally true( in)justices only
states of affairs, towards which some of these desires are directed). Desires
are something existing, that is: universal facts. Prohibitions, punishments and
intentions are also that, but they only exist desire-dependently.
The injustice = shalling-not-prevail =
should-not-be experience may be located in only one consciousness, but
exists admittedly-by-all, is a fact admitted by all. We think like this
of others' experiences in general, as far as we can perceive signs of them. I
emphasize: the suffering, that John experiences, is not "unjust for
John". The injustice = shalling-not-be is located in John's
consciousness, but the suffering is wrong l. shalling-not-be admittedly
by
all (all who apply
common sense), insofar as there are outsider-observable signs of the
shalling-not-be, that John experiences. (Isn't everything factual located only
somewhere?) Moral knowledge is objective in the sense "admitted by
all", but it must be gained by observing subjects. The experiences of
subjects are also its truth-conditions. -I admit, that this isn't the most
familiar form of objectivism, and therefore we'd perhaps better give it its own
name. I suggest "omnivoluntary objectivism".
Is this kind of moral philosophy of any use
in practical moral decisions? "Should-not-be experiences",
"allowed-to-be experiences" and "must be -experiences" all
exist equally. None of them is more real than the others. So, the same
situation can be both right (even required) and wrong. This is logically
unproblematic, since the requiredness and injustice exist in "different
locations", but practically problematic.
Morally only-right would only be the kind of
situation, where no subject has an intolerability-experience and all "must
be"-experiences are fulfilled. Interest-conflicts make this kind of
situation hard to achieve, even hard to strive for. The changing of a situation
intolerable to one subject may cause something intolerable for another. As an
extreme example: we can think of a sadist, who suffers intolerably, if she
cannot satisfy her compelling desire to torture a victim.
A morally only-acceptable situation may
(surprisingly?) only be an unattainable ideal, but at least we can pursue the rightest
possible situation. Let's think about injustices, things toward which
should-not-be experiences are directed. If there are (as it would seem) more
and less compelling should-not-be experiences, the objects of the first
mentioned are more wrong. In order to get an idea of what is most important to
avoid and pursue, we must judge, what things are experienced most important.
This is difficult and uncertain of results, but do we not anyway make our moral
decisions based on this kind of judgments (knowledge or beliefs concerning
priorities of the majority of humans or other animals)?
I will yet return to the prioritizations of
wrongs and rights. But now, again: can we consider a should-not-be experience
of a situation the factual and duty-creating shalling-not-be of the situation?
First: can we at all call the existence of a should-not-be experience
(without linguistic autocracy) a shalling-not-be? I claim that we can.
As an example we can think of the
(plausibly) most compelling should-not-be experience: the experience of an
individual, that her suffering (such as pain) is intolerable and has to cease,
it must not be. A should-not-be experience can just as well be named an
experience of ceasing-necessity.
Now: what else could a "necessity to
cease" mean than something resembling a compelling ceasing-desire -
even in moral contexts? When we talk about a moral necessity for the ceasing
of an injustice,
we clearly don't mean, that the injustice inevitably ends - ends of
logical or physical necessity. The inevitable ending of X would not oblige us
to make X end - it cannot be considered a demand to end. We mean (imagine)
something like that the world strives for the ending of the injustice,
without certain success - and does not merely idly pursue it, but screams
for the ending of injustice and is appeased only when it has ended. (We
feel that moral demands are compelling.)
From where would we be acquainted with this
kind of "scream", if not from suffering and compelling desire (or
unconditional intention)? The mind of the sufferer screams for the
ending of the suffering; a desire "towards" something screams
for its satisfaction. (A mere intention to perform an action doesn't, at
least to me, seem as a "compelling" directedness towards the action,
and I am not tempted to call it "a scream for the action".)
I find: if we can plausibly call the
objective "screams of the world", that we imagine,
"should-not-be:s", we can also call the similar (but
"local", not world-pervading) should-not-be-experiences
"should-not-be:s". -Someone may point out to me the obviousness of
the fact, that we don't , by our speech of injustice, refer to prohibitions or
punishments any more than an inevitable ending (and we don't consider them
morally obliging). I defend myself: I have discussed prohibitions and
punishments as potential "should-not-be":s, because they resemble
obliging demands remarkably more than actual inevitably-endings.
So, the "moral
ending-necessities", that we imagine, are (I claim) non-experiential as-if-desires.
Would we also acknowledge prohibitions and punishments (that exist
"objectively" = observably by everyone) as moral ending-necessities?
Even if we would, I claim that we experience also prohibitions and punishments
as "necessities not to do" only thanks to desires. They force us to
abstain from actions either thanks to the desire of the prohibitor, which
becomes our own desire, or our originally-own punishment-avoiding desire. I
would even say: we wouldn't recognize a prohibition as a prohibition (an
attempt to stop), if we didn't see the desire "behind the
prohibition". The prohibition is constituted by an attempt to stop
the prohibited action; there is no attempt or striving without a desire. (In a
possible soulless physical reality there is only happening and not-happening,
not striving for happening.) We can recognize a prohibition, an attempt to the
non-performing of an action, only where we observe a desire or
(desire-engendered) will that the action be not performed.
It seems, that the only thing, that
makes us classify something as a situation's shalling-not-prevail, is the
ending-desire directed at the situation - or a non-experiential as-if-desire.
Therefore: if there is a desire of the non-prevalence of the situation, there exists
a shalling-not-prevail of the situation. The shalling-not-prevail of the
situation is a fact. It is even a motivated (and thus morally relevant?) fact:
the ending-desire is a reason for demolishing the terrible. So is the
experience of intolerability - badness-experience! - that engenders it. (Above
I claimed, that badness is the only commonly acknowledged proof of injustice.)
-Whether a should-not-be experience leads to
a duty to end the shalling-not-be situation, I discuss later, in the chapter
"Obligation".
Once more: every should-not-be experience is
an existing should-not-be - a should-not-be fact, that everyone must
acknowledge. This can also be expressed in another way, with less violation of
language. When experiencing intense pain, the sufferer feels, that the ending
of her pain is unconditionally important, necessary. The moral
judgment of the sufferer may be, that the pain is acceptable (that God
would otherwise not condone it). But beside her moral judgment she has a lively
experience of the pain-ending necessity. In the mind of the sufferer, there
is an experience of the importance of the pain ending. So: the importance of
the pain ending exists. (What else could "important" mean than
experienced-as-important - or non-experientially as-if-experienced?) The
ending-importance exists, is a fact.
As a small rhetorical deviation: what could
be more compellingly important than that, which is experienced as the most
compellingly important: the relief from intolerable suffering, the satisfaction
of a compelling desire? If a non-experiential as-if-intolerability experience
and an as-if-ending-desire where directed at a situation, would the ending of
it be more important than the ending of something experienced as terrible,
painful (a pain-experience)?
I
still want to emphasize: a should-not-be-experience constitutes
injustice, a should-not-be judgment (injustice-judgment) doesn't.
A judgment, that says that a situation
should not prevail, is a belief in the universally-true shalling-not-be.
The belief is true only if there exists a shalling-not-be of the situation -
necessarily something else than the should-not-be belief itself. If a belief
refers to itself, we end up with an infinite regress: I believe, that there is
a belief, that the situation should not prevail, that is: that there is a
belief, that the situation should not prevail... What does "shalling-not
prevail" mean in the end? -If all moral judgments are desires projected on
the outer world, then all that is judged wrong is indeed wrong (and what is
judged required is required), but again thanks to the avoiding-desire, not the
moral belief. -It is possible, that a long-lived (from parents adopted?) belief
in the injustice of a situation makes the situation also detestable to the
injustice-judge, intolerable to her. In this kind of case the situation is - I
cannot deny it - indeed wrong. I'll return later to the practical consequences
of this.
* What would it
mean, that we refuse to infer justice from our
approval/acceptance/contentedness (even if our acceptance is the source of our
justice-views)? Let's imagine, that my interlocutor talks (now) to me about a
hypothetical situation H: I accept murder from any motive. If I don't (now)
conclude, that murder is right in situation H, I refuse inferring justice from
my acceptance. (If I would interpret "right" as meaning
"accepted by me", I could not deny the rightness of murder in
situation H.) In this case, wrongness would be to me "an object of
reason". Maybe Hume thought: in order to be convinced of an action's
injustice we must experience, that we perceive the injustice - perceive
in the action something, that we experience as wrong - we are not
satisfied by the knowledge, that we experience it as wrong.
Naturalism and
badness, that doesn't accept itself
So far I have
said: the injustice or requiredness of a situation is constituted by something
that is related to the situation: the "should-not-be
experience" = ending-desire or "must be -experience" = positive
desire directed at a situation in a human, animal or divine mind. This can
unproblematically be called moral objectivism (realism), insofar as the
existence of desires is opinion-independent. But can moral naturalism in
the sense of a kind of non-antinaturalism, be defended? Could the requiredness
or injustice abide in natural = intrinsical properties of actions or
situations - not in something, that is directed at them? (Requiredness or
injustice inherent in the action/situation itself could also be called objective
= in the object (action or situation) abiding requiredness or injustice,
independently of its experientiality. This is, by the way, already the fourth
here mentioned meaning of the word "objective".)
John L. Mackie (1977) has pondered on the
question in this vein (a translation from Finnish, italics mine): "The
claim, that there are some kind of objective values or inherently
prescriptive entities or properties, is in my opinion not senseless but
false. Plato's ideas give us a dramatic idea of what objective values would necessarily
be like. The knowledge of the idea of good gives the knower both an
action-direction and an overriding motive. The knowledge, that something is
good, tells the knower, that she should pursue it, and makes her actually
pursue it. An objectively good thing would be pursued by anyone, to whom it was
revealed. This isn't caused by any contingent fact, like that the perceiver or
the human race is genetically programmed to want the good thing, but thereof,
that the pursuing-admonition and pursuing-worthness are somehow contained in
the thing. Similarly, if there were objective principles of justice and
injustice, every (possible) wrong action would somehow contain its prohibition
and ending-worthness. Alternatively we would have to imagine something like the
fittingness-relations between situations and actions (proposed by Clarke), in
which case a certain kind of situation would always contain the demand of a
certain kind of action."
If Mackie's definition is changed into a
consequentialist one, concerning situations in stead of actions, there are (I
claim) "inherently prescriptive entities". There are states of
affairs/entities, that prohibit themselves from existing, and we have all
perceived instances of these. Suffering always contains the desire, that
the suffering be not (or at least end immediately).
So far I have, for the sake of convenience,
used the expression "suffering (intolerability-experience) that motivates
an ending-desire". Actually I think, that suffering and ending-desire
cannot be separated from each other. Or: there are ending-desires without
suffering, but not suffering without ending-desire. (Would we call such an
experience "suffering", whose subject finds it indifferent, whether
it continues or not?) Every experience of suffering contains its
"prohibition" = should-not-be experience.
Mackie wrote: an objectively good thing
would be pursued by anyone, to whom it was revealed. Reversely we could say: an
objective injustice (consequentialistically: a wrong situation) would be
avoided by anyone, who perceived it. As far as I can see, this also
applies to suffering. One can perceive suffering only by feeling it (in
others we only see signs of suffering). Everyone, who perceives = feels
suffering, gets motivated to end it, if she can (unless she pursues something
that she considers still more important by the aid of the suffering-inducing
thing). Adapting Mackie: the knowledge of a bad thing gives the knower a motive
to end it. (The motive isn't always overriding, but you can't have everything.)
Every suffering-experience contains a
suffering-"prohibition", desire that the suffering be not. Similarly:
every situation-intolerability-experience (that is not suffering)
contains a situation"prohibition", a desire that the situation prevail
not. This can be considered a weaker case of "intrinsicality", as the
prohibition is not contained in the situation itself. On the other hand: only
an experienced situation, situation experience (which the subject
perceives as an "outer world"-situation) can be experienced as
intolerable. Thus it can be said, that a situation = situation experience
contains the should-not-be experience. And expressly contains, I find (is not
merely "related to" the should-not-be experience). We don't
experience the intolerability here and the situation there, so I think we can
say, that the situation-experience contains the
intolerability-experience (or is characterized by intolerability).
Positive "must be:s" are less
applicable to the model. When there is a towards-directed desire, then the
desired experience or situation is not yet. Thus the positive desire is not
contained in the good itself, the desired experience or situation - only
in an unsatisfactorily thin idea of it.
But is this the only way to perceive it? I
find, that one can plausibly describe a positive desire as a continuing-and-strengthening-desire
of an experience (thought-content or sensation). If this is the case, then also
positive desires are prescriptions contained in the experienced (good). The
observed good (we can only perceive our own mind contents!) contains a demand
of its continuing and strengthening.
There are prescriptions inherent in bad
(stop, vanish!) and inherent in good (continue, strengthen!). It even seems as
though all prescriptions (desires) are inherent in good and bad. A
desire cannot exist in itself, it has to have an object. The desire is always
contained in an experience of the desired object (desired to attain or avoid).
In other words: the requiredness and
injustice are natural = intrinsical properties of situations = situation
experiences. In this sense my stance can be regarded as moral naturalism. And
also in the sense, that desires are properties/entities/relations perceivable
by the "natural" introspection ability.
In the (original?) introduction I proposed,
that my stance is objectivist/realist (as naturalism is a subspecies of
objectivism/realism) in the sense, that moral-fact constituents are independent
of opinions. So, do desires and suffering (that contains an ending-desire)
exist independently of their subject's opinions? Can the experience of the
existence of one's own desire or suffering be called an opinion? If we mean by
"opinion question" a question, that has several equally correct
answers, most would probably say No. It is commonly held (is a common
opinion?), that the subject is in a priviledged position to observe her own
experiences. Whether I or someone else experiences suffering, is at least not
commonly considered a question of opinion.
Finally: in the introduction I proposed as
the criterion of a moral position's naturalness (minimalistically), that the
position claims that requiredness or injustice is reducible to other than
pure moral value -properties. (At least this is a criterion for reductive
naturalism. The naturalist Cornell realists vouch for - I admit - the idea of
moral properties, that are natural = explanatorily potent in science, but not
reducible to e.g. psychology.) So, are the ending- and continuing desires,
which I consider constituents of the injustice and requiredness of situations, non-moral
properties of situation-experiences? I think we can answer in the affirmative.
We often talk about compelling desires - our
own or those of others - without making moral claims. Normally we don't
classify an experience, that something has to end, as a universally-true
(=moral) ending-necessity. The avoiding- and attaining-desire turn (for
us) into moral facts only (1) when we name them shalling-not-be:s and
shalling-be:s - without talk of "experiences" (when we see that
"shalling-not-be" and "shalling-be" only have an
application when they refer to desires or as-if-desires) (2) when we notice
their universally-true existence. Speech of desires is not in itself
moral speech, so I think we can claim, that the "wrong" and the
"right" in my position refer to the existence of something non-moral.
My position can, then, be classified as naturalism (omnivoluntary naturalism?).
Obligation
As I have (ad
nauseam) stated: there are shalling-not-be:s, ending-necessities
(negative desires) and shalling-be:s, continuing-strengthening-necessities
(positive desires). But does this lead to a duty-ethics? The experience of the
sufferer says only that the suffering should not be, not that something
must be done or refrained-from (that we have positive or negative duties).
Let's discuss this: do we have obligations
to (potential) sufferers?
Since I am looking for moral facts, I can
only appeal to facts: existing experiences.
Everyone, who experiences suffering, feels
that it should not be. We may plausibly continue: every sufferer feels, that
the actions leading to her suffering, should not have been performed. There
is an experience: suffering should not be caused - it is a fact, that
suffering should not be caused. (For the sake of convenience, I talk of
"suffering-causing actions", as if the actions were sufficient causes
of the suffering.)
But wait a minute: what if the sufferer
doesn't know, how her suffering is caused? What if someone has secretly put
anxiety-inducing chemicals in her coffee? What if the sufferer is an insect,
that doesn't know, that it is painfully crushed by another agent? In such cases
there is no "this suffering should not be caused"-experience. I call
this problem 1. Problem 2 is: before a certain suffering-instance is caused,
there is no desire for its not-being. (We don't live our lives thinking:
"I don't want to suffer in any way", so that we could be considered
to also want the not-being of the said suffering instance.) Yet my moral
intuition says, that causing suffering is wrong. So, is there a shalling-not-be
of suffering instance S before the existence of S?
I'll try again. Every suffering-instance is
shalling-not-be (contains its not-being desire). So, there should not be any
suffering. If there is a future: any present or future suffering should not be.
Let's suppose: if the action A is performed, suffering S is caused. Now: (1) S
should not be (2) if A, then S, so (3) A should not be.
The introduction of the deduction -
"any present or future suffering should not be" - can also be
considered a solution to problem 2. It applies to every suffering, even
future, that it should not be. But is the inference (1), (2), (3) credible? If
there is A, there is (soon) something that should not be, but is it
true, that A should not be? In advance we only know, that S should not
be (it contains a not-being desire). A is shalling-not-be only if A is S
(+ something else) - only if A contains S). Logic doesn't make
shalling-not-be (not-being-desire) stretch from S to something outside S. (Can
shalling-not-be be separated from desire and remain a fact?)
So, can we say that A contains S? If A is
first and S is next, there is a moment with A and without S. A cannot be
considered to contain S literally, like a whole contains its parts. (For
practical reason it is enviably apparent: if suffering should not be, then
suffering should not be caused.)
On the other hand, A is causing suffering
only thanks to that (and when) suffering comes into being. We can say, that
causing suffering should never happen, because it contains suffering. But why
should the action, before it becomes causing suffering, not happen?
Someone may counter me: A and S are
inseparable thanks to the causal relation (if A, then later S). S is always
included in the temporally extensive A-S-package. The package contains S, so it
should not be. But is even this true? Is the premiss (2) - "if A, then (always)
S" - ever true, if A is an action possible to human beings? Does any kind
of action (like theft or attempt at theft) always cause suffering? The
potential victim can often defend herself or influence, whether she suffers
from the caused situation. My experience tells me, that I can even rid my pain
sensations of painfulness by directing my attention to something else (or by
taking an analgesic).
Would it be better to define
suffering-causing counterfactually: if non-A, then non-S? A defense of negative
duties adapted to this requires expressing desire positively: non-S must be.
This is probably not a problem. I feel: my desire, that my present pain be not,
can just as well be expressed "the pain must be absent" as "the
pain should not be". The new formulation is: (4) in the future (also)
non-S must prevail (5) if no cause of suffering (A1, A2 ... An), action-natured
or not, then later non-S (6) there must prevail a situation with no
suffering-cause (A1, A2 ... An). A situation with no suffering can (in this
world) be realized only in the future and in a series of events, "entire
package", whose beginning does not contain suffering-causes. So, if there
should prevail a full suffering-lessness (at least in the future), then there
must be an "entire package" without suffering-causes.
Premiss (4) raises the question: if there
must, in future, prevail a full absence of suffering, does the present
situation non-A1 & A2 (from which follows non-S1 and S2) satisfy the moral
demands at all better than A1 & A2 (from which S1 and S2 follows)? If
suffering is in any case caused and (6) isn't realized, isn't it insignificant,
what I do? This I counter: there is no "cluster-desire" "There
must be non-S1 & non-S2 ... non-Sn", but only a number of independent
(actual and potential) non-prevailing desires of suffering. Some desires may be
satisfied (rightly) while others are not (wrongly). We had better replace
premiss (4) by another: there must be non-S1
& there must
be non-S2 ... there must be non-Sn.
The state of affairs is better in a
situation, where (in whose immediate past?) there are less causes of a certain
degree of suffering (or only causes of milder suffering) than in the
alternative situation. A smaller amount of suffering-causing actions is part of
a more just "entire package", that contains a smaller amount of
suffering in the final situation.
"Suffering-causing actions" don't
always cause suffering, but statistically it is true: less suffering-causing
actions, less suffering. So, if we compare large event-groups A and B, there is
less suffering in the event-group, where there are less suffering-causes
(actions or not). In the big whole a lesser suffering-amount is only realized
as part of an "entire package", where there are less suffering-causes.
So: if there must be as little suffering as possible, there must be an
"entire package" containing as few suffering-causes as possible.
In principle it is true: there must prevail
an absolute absence of suffering. Only this is only-right. Only right is an
"entire package", where the lifeless world and organisms together act
in a way, that causes total absence of suffering. In principle, even elementary
particles are obliged to strive for a full absence of suffering. However, as
elementary particles are known to be indifferent to their obligations, even I
abstain from directing moral demands at them. (Ethics is, finally, practical
philosophy.)
If I content myself with demanding or
recommending only the attainable = only that, whose realization my moral recommendations
even might further, I must formulate: there must be realized an
"entire, temporally stretched package", that contains a combination
of actions and inactions possible to agents susceptible to moral arguments,
whose result contains the smallest amount of (intolerable) suffering attainable
by their actions and inactions. (The smallest amount in the final situation of
the event-series, since it is impossible to change the past with human powers,
maybe even divine powers.)
Let's now assume, that the smallest possible
= smallest humanly attainable amount of suffering can only be realized by the
smallest amount of suffering-causing actions. So, the smallest amount of
suffering is always contained in an "entire package", an
event-series, in the beginning of which there is the smallest humanly possible
amount of suffering-causing actions. Ergo: if the most suffering-less possible
alternative must be realized, then there must be realized some "entire
package", which contains the minimum number of suffering-causing actions.
(Does the negative claim also apply: if there shouldn't be more
suffering, then there shouldn't be an entire package, that contains more
suffering-causing actions? Perhaps, but it was easier for me to show this by a
positive formulation.)
If refraining from causing suffering is not
necessarily the best means to minimize suffering, it is insignificant whether
(1) we avert suffering by refrainings or actions (2) we concentrate on
preventing or diminishing suffering. Again: humankind must perform actions
and abstainings, whose results contain the smallest possible amount of
(intolerable) suffering. Or - since no one can control the actions of all
humankind (the pragmatical viewpoint again) - every individual must perform
such actions (also cooperation- and law-initiatives), with which she can (with
some probability) realize the largest amount of suffering-preventing or
-diminishing.
In any case, the negative duties are not
obviously weightier than the positive ones. An action, which induces suffering,
may be justified, if we can by its aid prevent/satisfy a (more intense)
ending-desire or more intense suffering - or a more compelling positive desire
- and not increase the amount of future dissatisfaction. The
"increasing danger" is present, e.g., in our using other people as
suffering-combatting means against their desires. This can be expected to
weaken the trust between individuals, and what kind of consequences does this
have for individuals' willingness to cooperation? (Whatever the consequences,
everyone is obliged to refrain from autocratic suffering-inducing, if only
thanks to the principle of the suffering-minimum. If I cause someone to suffer,
the thus caused suffering-ending desire obliges me to help her also, so it is possible
that I could cause a better entire state of affairs by refraining from her
torturing and concentrated on helping others.)
The existence of positive duties, that I
touched on, seems like a tricky question, if we proceed from traditional
duty-views. Are we obliged to reduce suffering? The most part of the suffering
in the world would exist even without me - surely I am not responsible for
suffering, that I haven't caused? Surely it isn't my fault, that the world
exists?
In my view, even here we have to look for
the answer in facts, existing desires. One could defend the existence of
positive duties, in addition to the just said, like this.
Every sufferer wants unconditionally, that
her suffering end by any means possible, by the actions of whoever. (It
is possible, that the sufferer wouldn't accept all means, e.g. such, that would
harm her children. In making moral decisions, however, the exceptions are
relatively insignificant - there remains a broad spectrum of actions, whose
performing the sufferer may be said to unconditionally want and which her
children also tolerate.) It is experienced necessary - the necessity exists -
that someone/something help the sufferer.
But do cognitively simple animals have
desires for help? Do they have an idea of help or "whatever-ness", of
"whichever" means? Maybe we'd better stick to the
containing-necessity argument. That is: any time that someone/something
suffers, there is the ending-of-suffering desire, the ending-necessity. The suffering
must end, and its ending can only be realized by an "entire temporally
extended package", that contains suffering-ending actions of moral agents.
In other words: every moral agent must diminish suffering in the world as
much as she can. (I find the strictness of this proposition frightening, so
you may act wisely by being sceptical towards my following attempts to moderate
it.)
On the other hand: avoiding one's own
suffering is equally important as avoiding that of others. (Every
"self" experiences the ending and not-starting of her suffering as
important as everyone "else".) My own suffering is also the only
suffering, that I perceive directly - its existence is for me a more certain
fact than the suffering of other humans and animals, that (whose facades?) I
see.
Even
if we consider the existence and suffering of other minds facts: it is commonly
known, that excessive exertions can lead to painful exhaustion, deterioration
of cognitive capacities and illnesses. To which extent do we have to protect
existing resources - capacities and abilities of body and mind - in losing
which we lose (some of) our ability to reduce and prevent suffering, even our
ability to look after ourselves? Maybe I should formulate more leniently: from
everyone according to her capacity?
And what is my particular duty? It is surely
useful to consider, in which areas one's particular talents, skills, knowledge
and (for maintaining energy) interest objects would bring about the largest
amount of good. It is also useful to increase one's skills and knowledge. And
speaking of knowledge: since every subject knows best, when she suffers, she
herself can most speedily intervene with her causes of suffering. I dare to
recommend to everyone working for (also) one's own happiness and advancing in this.
The fact, that everyone is the most competent guard of her own happiness, can
be considered to lead to moderate egoism. (On the other hand, if we acknowledge
the significance of factual privilegedness - and deny solipsism - we must also
conclude, that everyone has a particularly weighty duty to help those, whom she
alone (in addition to the sufferer) knows to suffer.) From moderate egoism may
be inferred the desirability of an upbringing, which helps the child (or adult)
to develop as an independent problem-solver.
-I notice myself to support aims that are
popular even without me in the modern (western) world, at least on the level of
editorials. Is this worrying considering my independence of thinking? Actually
I do unconditionally support only these claims: 1. we can be held to be obliged
to avoid causing suffering 2. we can be held obliged to diminish suffering. To
what extent, is uncertain. In any case, I dare to recommend at least small
attempts at reducing the bad and undesired 3. in making moral decisions, it may
be useful to also remember the question of preserving capacities and the
privileged position of the sufferer as knower of her suffering (its existence,
existence time and ending-means). And the somewhat less privileged position of
everyone concerning the suffering in her immediate environment.
I ask you to notice, that moral facts -
existing desires - reveal directly only the absolute values and absolute
non-values, that must be pursued and avoided. Other grounds for moral
decisions I have explored too little to be a competent practical ethicist. With
other grounds I mean at least (1) what are the best means of attaining the
broadest possible satisfaction (2) to which extent we should use
satisfaction-increasing capacities now, to which extent preserve capacities for
future use.
The ideal
So far I have
mainly concentrated on negative norms and said: anything, of which it is
experienced that it shouldn't be, shouldn't be. Similarly we can say:
everything, of which it is experienced that it must be, must be (all
mental images, of which it is experienced, that they must be realized, must be
realized). The satisfaction of towards-directed desires is (often) equally
experienced as necessary - factually necessary - as that of suffering-ending
desires. If we acknowledge avoiding-desires as moral facts (obligating
shalling-not-be:s), consistency requires, that we also acknowledge
attaining-desires as such (obligating shalling-be:s). I for my part can't find
any counterargument for this. In addition, since the non-satisfaction of
positive desires regularly leads to suffering and its ending-desire, the
question "should morals be based also on positive desires" is finally
only an academic question (with all due respect to academies).
A perfect world, where everything would be only
right, would lack everything, that any subject livelily experiences as
shalling-not-be (intolerable). In a perfect world, all desires would be
satisfied immediately (and life would still be interesting and challenging. Or
rather brainless euphoria?). In our world, this is obviously hard to attain.
What should we then do in situations, where it is impossible to satisfy every
subject's positive and negative desires? Which are the desires (or desirers?),
whose satisfaction should be prioritized?
I postpone my answer a little, because I
suspect, that all readers do not even accept my model for a perfect world. In a
perfect world - there are no intolerability-experiences and all positive
desires are satisfied without delay? As far as I understand, ethicists rely
commonly on the rule: a moral system, that differs from the moral intuitions of
the majority of people, should be doubted if not rejected. It is admittedly
hard to find a person, whose moral sense would advise to obey all
avoiding-desires and positive desires - or a moral system, that would do so. In
its spirit my principle does, however, accord with the golden rule: treat
others the way you would want yourself to be treated. The aim to end all
intolerability-experiences and satisfy all desires is also an aim, which an
impartially empathetic creature would pursue - a creature, that wouldn't judge
from without: that is a superficial/immature/sick/selfish desire; you can
manage just fine without that).
The unfamiliarity of my principle is an
unavoidable result thereof, that the rule "satisfy all desires" is in
practice impossible to implement, if you aren't an omnipotent god (who is able
to place each subject in its closed virtual world). One could assume, that when
moral systems have been created, the creators have striven for practicability,
possibility to live by. A moral system is practicable only if it raises some
desires or aims - or desirers or aimers - above others in importance (and this
is just what I aim to do, too).
I suspect, that one important reason for our
spontaneous reactions against my principle is the strictness towards ourselves,
that we have learned when internalizing some of the moral systems of our world
of limited resources. Maybe also the pride in our willpower, that we feel when
abstaining from "sins". "With satisfying every desire we create
a society of good-for-nothings raised in cotton wool!"
-When saying, that the satisfaction of all
desires is important, I also mean future desires. If moral subject S wants to
eat food known as illness-inducing, we must decide, if this desire is more
important than S:s probable future desire to get well.
On the other hand: how fatal is the
incompatibility (or frictioned compatibility) with the moral intuitions of the
majority? The moral intuition of the majority is used as a moral touchstone
only in lack of a better one - since there "is not" any impartial
knowledge of right and wrong. The knowledge of avoiding- and attaining-desires is
this sought-for impartial knowledge. Avoiding- and attaining-desires are
shalling-not-be:s andd shalling-be:s, that exist admittedly by all. I suggest,
that we dismiss opinion-democracy and replace it by a democracy of desires.
The prioritization
of desires
Satisfying all
desires is, as admitted, only an unattainable ideal. How should we act in a
real-life situation, where the realization of a state of affairs is both
required and wrong? I already offered a tentative answer: we must avoid that,
which is most wrong. Now I motivate this a little.
So far I have said: what is experienced
important, is factually important. Consistently with this, we may continue:
what is experienced most important, is factually most important.
If there are several degrees of should-not-be experiences of
situation-experiences (which most would probably find obvious), the most
unconditionally shalling-not-be are those situation-experiences, which are
connected to the most unconditional should-not-be experiences, the most
compelling avoiding-desires. (Connected to these situation-experiences there
is the most unconditional necessity of the situation ending - these
situations are factually most necessary to end.) Reversely: most
important is the satisfaction of those positive desires, whose satisfaction is
experienced as most unconditionally important - the most compellling and
persistent desires. My experience tells me, that the non-satisfaction of these
also causes the most intense suffering (the most unconditional
avoiding-desire).
These premisses make it clear: if a
situation is both right = acceptable but no required, the injustice (wrongness)
is weightier. A positive avoiding-desire is weightier than an experience of
allowedness-to-be, of tolerating - in other words: lack of avoiding-desire. A
both wrong and allowable (to different subjects) situation must be treated as a
wrong one. Only a positive towards-desire can compete with an avoiding-desire.
Let's proceed to a more difficult question:
judging the intensity of desires. On what grounds can a moral agent consider
one desire more intense than another (if the desires are not her own)? For
starters I discuss, which avoiding-desires are more intense than others.
So far I have mainly spoken of
intolerability-experiences and ending-desires connected to suffering. I
admit, that there are other lively ending- and not-starting desires as well.
There are (2) losses of an unconditionally-wanted thing (a loved one, one's
moving ability, the respect of society), that lead to exclamations: this must
not happen (and regularly also lead to sufffering). There is (3) compassionate
"co-suffering", the intolerability of seeing another human or animal
sufffer. There are (4) experiences of the ugliness or grotesqueness of
landscapes, persons, actions and speech, that "deprive them of their right
to exist" (as the ugliness-experiencing person may jocularly formulate).
There are (even stronger than these?) feelings of disgust towards e.g. touching
dirt or insects. There are (6) disagreeable, but not painful sensations - bad
smells and tastes, irritating noises. There are (7) fears of suffering or other
intolerable things (also death) being realized in the future - and (8) fears of
their (assumed) causes (loss of job - loss of income - loss of tolerable life).
There are (9) decisions to perform actions, that lead to the desirer's
experience: "this must not happen", when the action is impossible to
perform. (10) The internalizing of a moral rule is, similarly, a decision to
not accept a certain situation or action (or to demand that it exist) - and may
lead to a kind of should-not-be experience - often (11) anger. Supporting a
moral rule is - I admit - often connected to (12) distaste towards an
"injustice" and desire that it end. (If the kind of projectivism
above presented is, at least sometimes, the right account for the genesis of
moral experiences, the distaste may even be the source of moral experiences.)
At first I ask, if I could simplify my task:
are some classes of the intolerable overlapping.
My personal experience is, that bad smells
and tastes are painful to experience - in extreme cases extremely
painful, in mild cases insignificant to moral discussions. Therefore I place
them in the class of suffering. (Yes: in my intensity-judgments I rely mainly
on introspection. This is only an opening to a discussion - others may come and
investigate the matter with a more scientific approach. For all I know, they
may have done so already.) Touching something disgusting (imagined or realized
touching), for its part, raises fear.
As an emotion, the fear towards causes
of something intolerable doesn't in my opinion differ from fear towards the
intolerable. I place different fears in the same class. Similarly: the
distaste towards a moral injustice (if it isn't co-suffering) doesn't differ,
as an emotion, from other ugliness-experiences - if not by being weaker
than they.
As far as I can see, co-suffering may be
erased from the list, if only because the situation that causes it is
intolerable in itself, thanks to the original suffering of the
"original sufferer" (if there is indeed original suffering, i.e. the
co-sufferer isn't wrong in her belief).
After these simplifications (I don't even
try to remove all overlappings), the list of intolerables looks like this:
1. suffering
2. losses of wanted
3. ugliness
4. the feared future/present intolerables or
their causes (in connection with activated fear, in situations where the feared
seems to approach or is present)
5. decision-contrary, non-accepted
neglecting of actions or moral injustices (also the non-realization of required
things)
6. causes of anger.
I admit: also
losses, ugliness-experiences and fears are often painful. However, I place them
in other classes than pains, because (according to my personal experiences)
they are not necessarily painful (even though they are non-desired). Even the
most painful loss, that of something unconditionally wanted, contains pauses in
the suffering - and the suffering is not as painful as pain-sensations or
anxiety can be.
Which of these are experienced as the
hardest to endure? I would say: I have the most unconditional should-not-be
experience, when I am experiencing intense suffering. Only then do I feel: this
MUST end (only this experience requires use of capitals). It's easy for me to
forget this when not suffering, but every intolerable pain or painful
experience reminds me of what is really important. I believe, that
internalizing this is a necessary condition for consistently moral acting.)
Factually most important would then be to
avoid causing, prevent, diminish and alleviate intolerable suffering.
At first glance this seems obvious, but is
it an intellectually honest claim? Even when I see intolerable ugliness I may
feel (even if it is only "detestable" and doesn't make me actually
suffer), that it must vanish. Could we say: in the former case my suffering
is intolerable, in the latter the ugliness, but the degree of intolerability is
the same? (Formerly I considered the answer: in the former case my experience
is intolerable, in the latter an external object. But even the ugly
object, that I see, is my experience.) Well - I leave the question to be
considered.
I think we can safely claim: a subject's own
extreme suffering is the kind of experience, that the subject cannot easily
demolish by directing her attention elsewhere (if it isn't obviously caused
by a certain object of attention, from which it is easy to detach one's
attention) like when seeing something ugly or (even) experiencing a difficult
loss. Common sense says: when the subject can easily end her
intolerability-experience, external help is less important. So, I propose: in
situations, where we cannot obey the "action injunctions" of
everybody's intolerability-experiences, we must prioritize those
intolerability-experiences, that their subjects experience as the hardest to
ignore. The practical conclusion stands: most important is the avoiding of
intolerable suffering.
I do not claim that it is easy to turn one's
attention away from losses, either (towards the remaining goods), but I find
that this is due more to lack of desire than lack of capability. Also: even
losses are connected to suffering as well as a situation-intolerability-experience,
but (as stated) at least in my case this has been milder than the suffering
connected to pain-sensations or anxiety caused by unconscious reasons. It would
be preferable, that difficult losses could be avoided, but I don't grant them a
priority-position among things to be avoided. Even seeing ugliness may cause
intense suffering, but this suffering is easily avoided by re-directing one's
attention.
I claim: easiest to ignore are things
contrary to one's decisions, including things judged as immoral. It takes an effort to attach to a decision -
letting loose of it takes none. Also: seeing ugliness is terrible, losses are
terrible, but seeing something judged as wrong is a weak experience, unless
it is strengthened by another intolerability, like co-suffering or an
intense ugliness-experience. Therefore I claim: morally condemned situations
are not to be included in the list of "factual injustices".
In
extreme cases, the feared intolerable is experienced as absolutely
necessary to avoid. If I want to be consistent, I cannot deny the moral
necessity to end the threats of the feared, or fears - regardless, whether the
fear is painful.
Is fear as difficult to ignore as
suffering-avoiding desires? The threat of something feared is also typically
hard to ignore - often morally unwise as well, since the feared is experienced
as intolerable at the latest when realized. Maybe we should judge threats of the
feared according to the intolerability-degree of the realized feared -
give up treating them as an independent injustice-category?
This might be motivated, if there were no
irrational fears. By these I mean fears, whose object is intolerable for the subject
in no other way than its feared-ness. For me the fear of the dark has been like
this: after letting go of the thought "I must away from here,
immediately" and replaced it with the thought "I am here, fully"
I noticed, that there was nothing unpleasant in being in the dark. A more
universal case of something feared, that is not painful when realized, is
death.
So, I think that threats of the feared
should be preserved as their own injustice-category. Does their
injustice-degree differ from the injustice-degree of suffering? My personal
experience says, that conquering fears is easier than the experiencing of
pain-sensations as painless (even the latter is possible, but requires notably
more expertise). So, I grant suffering a higher injustice-degree than fears.
(Personally at least I have felt, that even the most intense fear isn't actual
suffering. At most, an unremitting attempt to flee leads to painful
exhaustion.)
We have yet to discuss the category of
anger-reasons. Anger is typically directed at persons, not situations - often
persons, who have done something morally condemned by the anger-subject. When
getting angry at someone for moral reasons I feel, that a) the existence of
the perpetrator is intolerable b) the perpetrator's lack of remorse
and neglect of rectifying the action's consequences, when possible for
the perpetrator, is intolerable.
If no one or nothing experiences the
existence, remorselessness etc. of the perpetrator intolerable independently
of her moral judgment, I am wrong in my judgment of the injustice of these.
Most right would be, that I would become aware of the groundlessness of my
judgment and calm down. (Factually most right? Who experiences so? I
claim this, because the ending of every should-not-be experience rectifies some
injustice - and because noticing an error is an easy way to end a should-not-be
experience.)
Still: as long as my anger - a lively
should-not-be experience - exists, it must be considered a constituent of
injustice. (Yes: even the injustice of the existence of the perpetrator. I
remind you, that situatiuons can be simultaneously wrong and required.) So,
what is the intensity-degree of anger-reasons as injustices?
According to my experience, my anger is always
a consequence of my thinking: that should not be. So, injustice-judgments are
apt to arouse anger. Surely there are other anger-reasons as well: if I
experience myself to be judged without grounds, I get angry, because I expect
others to perceive me the way I am. After all, my strengths are visible to
everyone! After all, we live in a shared world! (I feel, that others should
see things as they are. Yet I wouldn't call this a moral
judgment, but a
lively "should-not-be"-experience.
My anger is caused by the thought:
"that should not be", and by my holding on to the thought. I
"cannot" let go of the thought of the situation's prohibition (by me)
and let the situation prevail - even as a starting-point, that I could
try to rectify. My point is: as soon as I fully admit to myself, that the
bad situation prevails - when I stop struggling against it in my mind
- my anger ends. Looking the fact in the eye demolishes the anger. (This
also applies to anger caused by general irritability. But how can I venture to
claim, that anger is always caused in this way? Simplifying a little:
that only a persistent holding on to a thought can engender pressure, that
sometimes erupts as violence, seems to me intuitively as obvious, as it is
logically obvious, that all single men are unmarried. Those, who think this a
groundless claim, I counter: logical apparency is in the end as ungrounded as
intuitive apparency.)
Anger is easy to control with a decision to
acknowledge a fact as a fact - according to my experience notably easier than
to control physical suffering, loss anxiety or fears. Therefore I give it a low
injustice-degree. Yet, since even anger control requires a little expertise, it
should be harder to ignore than ugliness-experiences or (non-anger inducing)
things contrary to decisions.
I must admit: for a person, who isn't
familiar with anger management techniques, conquering anger is just as unattainable
a goal as pain-management by mental methods. In spite of this, the low
injustice-degree of anger-reasons may be grounded: as an intense feeling, anger
only lasts a little while at a time. Nature rectifies rapidly the injustice of
anger-reasons, if anger alone constitutes the injustice of these.
My tentative order of injustices, from the
most to the least to-be-avoided, is then:
1. suffering-reasons or suffering
2. threat of feared or fear (also objects of
disgust or disgust)
3. loss of unconditionally-wanted or
non-acceptance of loss
4. anger-reasons or anger
5. ugly objects (or sounds) or
ugliness-experience
6. decision-contrary (also moral-contrary)
situations or decisions (morals?).
Most uncertain I
am of the order of 2. and 3.
What about the intensities of positive
(towards-directed) desires? Many a materially privileged person would surely be
ready to say, that sexual desire is the most intense. I suspect, though: after
having starved (of food) most people would even be tempted to eat dirt or other
normally unappetizing objects. The intensity of bodily desires (I don't say
"needs" * (note in end of this chapter)) seems to correlate strongly
with the duration of their non-satisfaction.
In any case, fact remains: sexual desire is
(for many, often) compelling - even at its start. So, the desirers (factually) have
to get an opportunity of satisfying it. This also applies to young people
(even children), the aged, the disabled and different kinds of institution
interns - and to desires during work- or school-hours.
Sexual discrimination of minorities is (I
believe) growingly condemned also in Finland - though many a parent seems to
have a forceful opinion of an age limit, under which a child "cannot"
compellingly want sex. The sexual rights of animals I haven't even noticed
being discussed. Do we really believe, that animals don't experience compelling
desire or suffer from sexual abstinence? Often a family has only one pet, whose
sexual advances towards its owners are coldly rejected (!). (I won't even start
to discuss the sexual rights of production animals.) So, if a dog wants to
relieve its sexual pressures against the leg of its owner, should it be allowed
to do so? Fact-morals says: yes, if there are no weighty reasons to the
contrary. The mild
embarrassment of
the owner is a light-weight counterargument to the imperative of animal lust.
When ethics and etiquette conflict with each other, etiquette must give in!
(This raises the question of the justification of rapes. For my part I venture
to generalize, that masturbation is sufficient to relieve all the possible
desire, whose intensity exceeds the intensity of the rape victim's desire to
get rid of her suffering. After all, most right is a situation, where both the
sexual desire and the suffering-avoiding desires of both parties are satisfied
or not-even-started.)
I think we can claim reasonably safely, that
desires caused by bodily sensations, including desire of (non-sexual) touch,
are harder to ignore than e.g. the desire to possess (non-sexually) a beautiful
object. It is harder to turn away one's attention from one's bodily sensations
than from outer-world objects. Therefore I place bodily desires (so-called
needs, that also maintain good health - resources of producing good) before the
latter (so-called whims). I do the same with the desire of action and desire of
company, for humans and many other species. (The desire to rest I don't
classify as a positive desire, but as a desire to avoid suffering, painful
struggling when tired.) Otherwise I don't have much to say about positive
(towards-directed) desires. Others may investigate the matter more thoroughly.
Maslow's hierarchy of needs, for example, answers a question similar to mine:
which desires become ignored thanks to other, more powerful desires. It's
difficult to get closer to a quantification of desires.
In sum: of all injustices most wrong is a
suffering, which isn't in an apparent way caused by an object of attention
(like an ugly object) that is easy to ignore (placed outside the sufferer's
body), and the non-satisfaction of the most compelling (bodily?) desires. So,
most weightily required is demolition or prevention of such positive and
negative desires.
Suffering is painful and its ending
increases pleasure; the non-satisfaction of compelling desires is painful and
their satisfaction increases pleasure. Therefore: hedonistic utilitarians are
right! (Well, at least roughly.) Most right is a situation, that contains least
suffering and most pleasure. Aesthetic moral systems (like the one of
Nietzsche) are wrong: no one experiences the valiance of life or human
as more important (or as less ignorably important) than the ending of her own
intolerable suffering. Liberalist ethics are wrong when permitting individuals
to fight with each other or otherwise induce pain in one another. When
experiencing pain, everyone feels, that it "shouldn't be". Only
future pain can be ignored.
In hedonist-utilitarian terms: increasing a
pleasure less than perfect is always morally required. Every subject, whose
pleasure isn't absolute, wants a more full pleasure. I venture to claim
so, because I find: a less-than-perfect pleasure is mingled with pain - and
every sufferer wants to get rid of her suffering. So, the desire to increase
one's pleasure and the desire to get rid of one's (intense) suffering can both
be classified as suffering-avoiding desires. The avoiding-desire of intense
suffering is, one could assume, more unconditional than the avoiding-desire of
mild suffering. Therefore: demolishing intense suffering is more
unconditionally important than perfecting pleasure (in situations, where we
must choose). In a utilitarian calculus we must give more weight to the
demolishing and preventing intense suffering (i.e., I support negative
utilitarianism, insofar as we only consider desires concerning pleasure and
suffering).
If intense suffering and imperfect pleasure
are seen as points in the same (suffering-)continuum, it gets impossible to
think of doing good as a zero sum game (where the result is a neutral zero, if
a value of +5 somewhere is added to the value of -5 elsewhere). Nothing can
reduce the injustice of intense suffering.
I also claim: the ending of intense
suffering for one subject is more important than the ending of milder suffering
for many. Let's imagine a starting point situation, where the suffering value
for one subject is 8 (intense suffering), and that of five others is 2
(uncomfortableness) each - and two different development models: a) the suffering
value of all five "2-sufferers" is turned to zero (unmarred
happiness) and the experience of the "8-sufferer" is let to stand b)
the suffering value of the "8-sufferer" is lowered to 6 and the
"2-sufferers' " experiences are let to stand. In the development a)
the injustice of the whole is not diminished from the starting point. It is
still wrong with the weight of an eight: there is an injustice of eight.
In situation b) there is no injustice greater than that of six, so it is less
wrong.
We mustn't add the suffering values of
different subjects together and see, how many extreme should-not-be experiences
they form - after all, mild sufferings do not factually form extreme
suffering (or mild pleasures extreme pleasure). The situation with the highest
single suffering value is most wrong.
So, is it right to lower one subject's
suffering value from eight to seven by giving ten happy subjects a 7-value of
suffering? I must answer: per se, yes. In practice this is not
necessarily most right, since the suffering-reasons of the formerly happy might
notably weaken their powers and ability to cultivate good in the future. (I am
also afraid, that legalizing "sacrificing" people for others' sake
would lead to general fear, lack of trust between people and fleeing from
happiness-guards, maybe to alternative societies.)
Estimating intensity of suffering is
difficult, but if we want to act most right possible and if the
injustice-degree of situations depends on the intensity of suffering, we cannot
avoid making estimating-attempts. In moral decision-making we are forced to act
based on uncertain knowledge (unlike in business, politics, agriculture and
nursing?).
Even in this country, a common but rarely
discussed case of getting a small gain to many on the expense of a few is the
noisy night delivery of mail. There are people who cannot, after being awakened
by a delivery person's stamping in the staircase, go to sleep again before
morning and get-up time. Even if these persons would only form one per mill of
sleepers, this would make noisy night delivery a weighty injustice. For
someone, who has slept many hours too little, her entire following day may be
anguish - in practice all her life, since night delivery is continual.
* Speaking of
"needs" seems to me to confuse the matter needlessly (no pun
intended). In my view, when we say "she needs X" we often mean:
"she must have X, so that she can have/preserve Y, that she is entitled
to. (X can be, for example, the condition of health, survival or a tolerable
life.) Desires and wishes are located simply in the mind of the
desirer and wisher. Need, on the contrary, is something, whose
"satisfying" the speaker considers morally required. Like I
have said, requiredness cannot be motivated by a belief of requiredness without
ending in infinite regress. -Sure, we talk about "needs" also in
other meanings - we say: Vivian needs a key (in order to enter her apartment, which
she aims to do - the "needed" is a means of gaining what the
"needer" aims to gain - but these meanings are hardly relevant to
moral discussions.
Order of desirers
(sic)
Since the
philosophical attitude says: let nothing be held certain without thinking, I
must also discuss this: can subjects be put in importance order?
The only unconditional moral norms, that
follow from the aforesaid, are the avoiding of intolerable suffering and
satisfying compelling desires. The satisfaction of compelling positive and
negative desires is always unconditionally important (=experienced as
unconditionally important), no matter, the desire of whom or what is in
question. The compelling desires of all subjects - the ugly and the beautiful,
the stupid and the intelligent, the soulless or the soulful, humans and animals
- are unconditionally important to satisfy (or demolish). Also: avoiding the
suffering of the dishonest is as important as that of the honest! Avoiding the
suffering of adults is as important as that of children! Avoiding one's own
suffering is as important as that of others.
Even the worst torturer/criminal experiences
the ending of her suffering as unconditionally important - there is its
unconditional importance, its unconditional importance is a fact. By
punishing criminals we aim, of course, (also) at preventing crimes, but the
morally best alternative would be to prevent crimes without punishments. Such
alternatives must be (and has been) investigated. I also think, that in order
to prevent vengefulness, we should painstakingly emphasize the injustice of all
suffering, when raising children.
Similarly: an adult experiences her
suffering as just as intolerable as a child her own = avoiding it is as
important. Subjecting an adult to a suffering-inducing situation is more
acceptable than that of a child only if the adult is capable of suffering
less from the situation - on short or long term - than the child would
suffer. Surely this is a more common state of affairs than its opposite.
But we can also imagine a scenario, where an adult will be embittered (and
forget morals?) for the rest of her life, if (for example) giving up a new life
partner candidate, "the one", for the sake of her children. The
weightiness of conflicting desires (I still don't say "needs"*) must
be estimated individually in all different cases.
I cannot refrain from warning of going to
extremities in this direction, either - of over-emphasizing the
"rights" of adults. Leaving small children in the care of others for
the duration of their parents' (weekend-)vacation is, or can be, weightily
wrong, perhaps most wrong, when the substitute carers are not continuously
carers of the child (in an extended family or commune).
I myself was left in the care of my
grandmother for the weekend (really only the weekend? That's what my parents
have said) when I was 2 - the only event of that time, that I can remember. As
soon as my parents had left, I started to wait for them (whatever else I did) -
perhaps partly therefore, that my mother had told me that they wouldn't be gone
long. The vain waiting soon turned into anguish and my energy was consumed by
imagining my parents coming back, so that all action became intolerably heavy
for me. That is, I began to suffer from clinical depression (retrospective
self-diagnosis). The experiences of day-care center children I can only make
guesses at. A separation from one's nearest may be small potatoes for an adult,
but for a (normal? exceptionally attached? one encouraged to wait?) child
living hell. As a crumb of practical philosophy: if the parents want rest,
maybe they could engage a babysitter and stay home?
The alone-importance of satisfying
compelling desires leads to the equality of subjects. Or does it? Even this
inference would be possible: most unconditionally important is the satisfying
of those subjects, whose positive desires and intolerability-experiences are
the most intense. The passionate first!
The conclusion is inevitable, if only
a part of subjects are capable of extreme (e.g.) suffering experiences. This is
hardly evolutionary-psychologically credible. For example, avoiding bodily
mutilation is so important for the survival of the individual, that big
differences between individuals in its intolerability-degree cannot be
expected. And even if there would be great variations, in practice it is
difficult to find out, whose intolerability-experiences are the most intense.
Making assumptions in the matter is easy and dangerous. In her novel
"Uncle Tom's Cabin" Harriet Beecher Stowe draws an uncomfortably
familiar picture of a lady, who thinks: "The black (slaves) don't have the
kind of family feelings that we do" and (consistently) interprets Mammy's,
who has been separated from her children, joyless appearance as
"sulking".
Self admiration soon alone inclines many to
believe, that all their experiences (or those of their tribe) are more intense
than those of others. It is hardly wise to strengthen this inclination by moral
systems, that emphasize differences in intensity of emotions/desires. And
independently of this, epistemological difficulties make it best to avoid all
probable intolerability-experiences of all subjects.
The last said raises one more question. It
is best to avoid the intolerability-experiences of all subjects
(experiencers), the suffering of all sufferers. But who or which are
sufferers? Animals cannot tell us about their possible sufferings verbally,
often not unverbally either. Fish, reptiles or invertebrates cannot scream of
pain and they have no muscles, that produce facial expressions. However
assiduously we investigate, we cannot be sure of their ability to suffer. How
do we know, that the behaviour patterns of animals, that in us are connected
with pain (rubbing the damaged body part in crustaceans, the (ostensible?)
attention's turning away from the outer world in fish, self dosage of
analgesics in rats - cf. Braithwaite 2010) only occur in connection with experienced
pain? All experience contents could logically also exist as non-experiential
(and affect their "subjects' " behaviour?) as long as we cannot
define the difference of "experience" and "non-experience"
(phenomenon and non-phenomenon).
We cannot be sure, but wouldn't it be
terrible (factually terrible!) to cause suffering in a creature, that we have
suspected of being able to suffer, because of lack of certainty? My common
sense also says: the ability to experience pleasure, pain and desire is
nature's incentive, that makes an organism pursue certain situations and avoid
others. A moving organism, that wouldn't have pain sensations, would get
mutilated frequently. If a "mechanical" stimulus-reaction chain would
suffice to move animals, why do even humans have experiences? (Well - maybe
suffering is needed to motivate the most intelligent animals to choose the best
damage-avoiding strategy, and only in these animals motion requires decision?
Or maybe it is needed, when the animal is affected by several, conflicting
stimuli, so that the animal can make avoiding the biggest evil its priority? If
this is the case, e.g. trouts and some crabs are obviously sensate (op. cit.).
Epiphenomenalists don't
believe in the ability of desires and moving-attempt(-experience)s to cause
bodily movements, but think of them as evolutively meaningless by-products of
certain brain events. To them I say: (1) pleasure and suffering, that are
temporally connected to our
desires, are just
the kind of experiences, that could make us perform pursuing- and
avoiding-movements. If I experience something as terrible, I naturally want
to avoid it. Isn't it quite a coincidence, that brain events leading to motions
induce as their by-products just this kind of (=value-natured) experiences? (2)
Even if desires, suffering etc. wouldn't have causal power, humans have
them during certain brain processes - do we have any reason to suppose, that
other animals haven't? (Of course, this is not conclusive proof.)
I suggest the rule: if it seems to be
directed by its perceptions, it might be able to desire and suffer. Of what,
remains undecided. Clues to this can be had by observing, how the
organism(-species) acts in its natural habitat, where it has more opportunity
of choice than e.g. at a farm. But can we be certain, that production animals
and pets want to live like their wild counterparts?
Since Per Jensen's studies in the 1970's,
research has suggested that domestic animals act very much like the wild
variants do, if they have an opportunity to do so. (Jensen's domestic pigs
poked about in the ground, formed social groups etc.) What is important to
domestic animals, has also been investigated by giving them freedom of choice.
Even that, how important the animals consider different things, can be
investigated by observing, how much of an effort they are ready to make in
order to get different privileges. We don't need to base our actions on guesses
alone.
When keeping pets and production animals, we
should keep in mind at least these possible sources of suffering and
unsatisfied desires: pain, noise, unsuitable temperature, unsuitable (for
action or rest) lighting, bad smells, bad-tasting or unsuitable food; lack of
nutrition, water, oxygen, rest (an undisturbed sleeping environment), of sex,
touch or other company, of action or variation; loss of "spouse",
"children", "parents" or familiar carer; restriction of
moving. (I'm sure I forgot something essential - I'm sorry.) We act
mostly-right only if we arrange for the animals an environment, that they would
choose for themselves - according to best possible research - on every point of
the checking-list. I claim so, if only because the satisfaction of animals'
desires is equally important as that of humans (which is important!). The
desires of animals are equally compelling - at least I haven't found any good
reason to believe otherwise (cf. Vilkka 1996).
Making animals' desire-satisfaction possible
on all points may make the keeping of production unprofitable. If so, the moral
inference is easy: we must give up keeping production animals. Which desires do
we think are more easily ignored: the humans' desire to have meat, fish, eggs,
milk or leather or the animals' pain-avoiding desire (castrations without
anaesthesia) or sleep deprivation, the desire to run and leap, the desire to
mate, the desire to touch another animal, the desire to keep one's offspring
near, the desire to generally do something (other than peck or bite a
companion)? The question may be falsely put: we don't know, that animals would
even try to ignore their desires. If they don't try, they certainly don't
succeed in doing so. All desires of animals are to their subjects
impossible to ignore. If I want to be consequent, I can only make this
conclusion: if animals don't try to ignore their desires, the satisfaction of
animals' desires is more important than that of humans.
The desires, that must be weighed against
each other in the animal production question, are specifically the animals'
desires to (in aristotelical terms) realize their species- or
individual-essence and the humans' desire to eat good-tasting meat (or dress in
good-looking and -feeling leather). A human doesn't need animal nutrition to
stay healthy (Foer 2011), perhaps with some exceptions (the multi-allergic,
persons whose organism doesn't produce certain fatty
acids).
Animal production has also been defended by
employment considerations, in which case we must compare the animals' desire to
species-typical behaviour with the ex-farmers' need to get a new profession or
(at worst) unemployment. In my view, even here there's no real competition.
Even if we would arrange the animals' living
circumstances in essential parts (according to best research essential) like
the circumstances in nature, there would remain serious moral problems. First
the problems in research: can a human with her sensation idiosyncrasies and
other experiential idiosyncrasies even imagine all things, that are important
to other species - ask the right questions? (Or, on the other hand: are the
researchers inclined to excessive avoiding of anthropomorphism - e.g. to
assume, that other animals don't suffer from an ugly environment?) Can we, in
our choice-experiments, offer the animals sufficiently many alternatives to
find the one that animals would choose - even many enough moving-space size alternatives?
Do economical interests, or the researchers' ideas of what kind of improvements
are feasible (without giving up animal production), control the research? Even
at its best research only yields knowledge thereof, what the average members of
a species want - what about exception individuals? And exception moods of
average animals?
Above I said, that everyone is the most
alert guard of her own happiness. When restricting an animal's freedom to move
we lessen its ability to guard its own happiness - satisfy its desires and
escape from its sufferings, as soon as they surface. Restricting freedom
increases the danger of unsatisfied desires. So, is it justified without
weighty reasons (like circumstances, where the survival of humans depends on keeping
animals)? Even classical utilitarianism considers as the right action the
action, that guarantees the greatest amount of pleasure (or the best possible
pleasure/suffering balance) among all subjects. A procedure, that specifically
increases the danger of suffering (stronger suffering than meat-deprivation
induces in humans) is hardly in accordance with this view of right acting
either. Sure, even wild animals often suffer (from nutrition-deprivation,
droughts etc.), but this doesn't disprove the argument. After all, we don't
take production animals from nature and save them from even worse
circumstances. By
breeding
production animals we create new sufferers in addition to the animals, that
suffer in nature. (Wouldn't the ethically sustainable inference rather be, that
we must help wild animals?) It is hard to justify breeding animals in
captivity, if we cannot show meat production etc. to be an alternative for
something even worse.
The breeding of animals is made even more
problematic by the fact, that even the nowadays common level of happiness of
animals depends on the carers. If a carer develops clinical depression and
loses the energy to give her animals food and water, the animals can only
suffer passively. This and similar dangers are always present in keeping
animals, particularly so, when there is only one carer. Can we accept this, if
the danger is realized in this country, say, at five farms a year? Or, rather:
can the animals endure it? Can they endure the deliberate pain-inducing in
slaughterhouses (where power, there misuse!) and the "unfortunate
accidents" due to the "effectiveness" of the slaughter
procedure? Above I ended up with the conclusion, that it is more important to
avoid the extreme suffering of a few than the mild of many. It should be safe
to continue: it is more important to avoid extreme suffering of a small number
than to guarantee the culinary pleasures or keeping of profession for a large
number.
Someone may observe to me, that we can never
remove all injustices from the world; we can legislate and try to enforce laws,
but all crimes and accidents can never be prevented. This is true in itself,
but in my view the keeping of production animals is connected to the
possibility of exceptional suffering-inducing. Not many criminals deprive their
victims of moving freedom for a long time so that the victim cannot provide
herself with food and drink (at least not many outside prisons, in peacetime,
in Finland). The easily-ignorable desire of a human to have meat, cheese or ice cream doesn't
justify (according to any kind of utilitarian calculus not restricted to
humans) exposing animals to the danger of extreme suffering.
-The last said raises the question: what is needed
or necessary suffering-inducing or exposing to suffering? When we talk
about "needed" or "necessary" suffering we proceed from the
premiss, that the suffering-inducer pursues something, that is more important
than avoiding the induced suffering - possibly, that it is more important to avoid
the additional work or monetary expense, that would prevent the suffering
(e.g., that fish "cannot" be killed individually on a trawler, but
can be left to suffocate). Fact-morals says, though, that nothing is more
important (less ignorably important) than avoiding suffering and satisfying compelling
desires. So, justified would be the kind of use of animals, that satisfies
compelling desire of food, sex etc. (beasts of burden, hunting dogs...?). And
would fighting climate change justify replacing tractors and cars with real
horsepowers? I believe, that many an ideal-utilitarian calculus would say Yes.
Keeping horses in cramped single-stalls it surely doesn't justify. The animal
must be able to move and socialize when the animal wants, not when it is
convenient for the human.
Last words of
defense
Above I have, I
believe, consistently claimed, that phenomenal situations
(situation-experiences, that contain desires), above all, are wrong or required
- they, the consequences of actions, can make actions wrong or required. (Of
course, a should-not-be experience or has-to-be experience can even be directed
towards the action itself.)
In everyday speech we call "wrong"
or "required" above all actions - maybe only actions. H.A. Prichard
(2010) thought, that in correct moral speech we never say "it should be so
and so", but the expression is misuse of language. Here I disagree with
Prichard.
If we make clear to ourselves, what kind of
properties we mean by "injustice" and "requiredness", we
may well end up saying, that even situations (states of affairs) can have these
properties. In my view, this is exactly the case: by "injustice" we
mean truly-admitted-by-all existing shalling-not-be; an existing
shalling-not-be (that we can observe) can only be a should-not-be experience or
something caused by a should-not-be experience (prohibitions etc.): there are wrong
states of affairs = the kind of existing-instances of (object-)experiences,
that contain a should-not-be experience (painful experiences and other
intolerability-experiences).
A required state of affairs is the
kind of existing-instance of (object-)experience, that contains a
must-be(-and-strengthen)-experience - an object of positive (=towards-directed)
desire. And a right = permissible state of affairs is the kind of
existing-instance of an (object-)experience, that doesn't contain a
should-not-be experience.
Another point, where my language use differs
from the usual, is that, that I don't call any situation only wrong, only
right or only required. Isn't this, at least, misuse of language? Isn't
it essential to our understanding of "required" or "wrong",
that actions or situations are only required or wrong? I don't know -
experiences of essentialness vary between individuals. But this kind of defense
occurs to me: "requiredness" and "wrongness" is essentially
shalling-be and shalling-not-be. If we can find in the world something
(also-)shalling-not-be and (also-)shalling-not-be, we have found something
required and something wrong. We have only been mistaken in our belief,
that the required would be only-required and the wrong only-wrong.
In any case, the "both-a-and-b-ness"
doesn't make my moral system impracticable - we can decide, which situations
and actions are most required and most wrong. Or am I entitled to speak of
"required", "wrong" and "moral system"? I correct
myself: my idea construction is practicable - it permits us to decide,
which situations and actions are the most necessary admittedly-by-all
and the most shalling-not-be admittedly by all. (Perhaps not a moral
system, but better than nothing?)
A more serious accusation of language misuse
might be this: I demand the language user to call "shalling-not-be" a
situation, that someone else experiences as shalling-not-be. (I have
already discussed this, but I repeat it because of the importance of the
matter.) In real life we never use language in this way. We only use the
expression "should not be/prevail" on our own account - meaning
"I want it to not be/prevail".
I deny the latter claim. In the beginnning
of the text I concluded, that in moral language use "wrong" refers specifically
to a shalling-not-be independent of our desires - to an objective or
universally-true shalling-not-be. In moral discussions we talk continually
about a shalling-not-be that is independent of our own desires.
"The shalling-not-be of X" we
understand (I venture to generalize) to mean, that something screams for
the ending of X - just like (or almost like) in connection with the avoiding-desire
of X. Therefore we can plausibly call avoiding-desires
"shalling-not-be:s". Or can we? Normally we don't acknowledge the desires
of individuals as shalling-not-be:s. I believe, though, that the reason for
this is only the fact, that we don't consider desires universal
shalling-not-be:s (because "they cannot all be true at the same
time"? because they are local?). I think that I have
shown above, that
shalling-not-be:s etc. constituted by desires (claims of them) are
universally true. The desires exist admittedly by almost everyone. We use
language quite correctly when calling something experienced as
shalling-not-be "shalling-not-be (and "morally
wrong", insofar as the should-not-be experience is also motivated by
badness - which I consider it always is).
In moral thinking we always long for
universally-true shalling-not-be - we just haven't noticed, that a
should-not-be experience (of another subject or ourselves) is like this.
In spite of this (once more): are the
"shalling-not-be:s" that I have proposed (objects of desires) morally
required? A negative answer can be motivated in at least two ways in addition
to the already-mentioned.
(1) We call (and are ready to call?)
"moral norms" only demanderless demands and desirerless
desire-like things (2) above I have accepted as a ground for moral injustice
anything bad-for-someone/something, whose ending someone/something wants. But
most would seem to think, that the desires of one individual (or whims of
anyone) are not moral grounds. The name of "ground for moral
injustice" is deserved only by something, that is more harmful than
beneficial for the well-being of the entire society - or the highest
preferences of the entire society. (I for my part assess first the (moral?)
injustices, and only "afterwards" estimate the weightiness of
injustices in the big whole.)
It is hard to impugn these observations.
Perhaps I don't, indeed, succeed in defending moral objectivism. But
this doesn't make me seriously worried.
I think I have shown, that the shalling-be
and shalling-not-be of certain situations are universal facts. There
is a shalling-end of certain situations - a compelling ending-desire - so
everyone must admit, that these situations factually must end. And
anyone must care for their ending, if her powers allow it. (Everything
desired-to-end must end - in lack of better, the greatest possible part of it -
and the ending of most possible desireds-to-end is only realized in an event
series, in whose beginning moral agents strive for the ending of
desireds-to-end.) I consider this - the requiredness admittedly-by-all - more important
than the question, whether this is moral requiredness.
Actually, something "universally-truly
shalling-not-be" is in a stronger sense shalling-not-be than the
"morally wrong", insofar as the latter only means something
specified, like "harmful to general well-being". From the fact, that
an action "harms general well-being", it only follows that we must
refrain from the action if we pursue general well-being. Conditionally,
not categorically.
Everyone may not admit, that the word
"should" has a referring meaning. Those who don't, I ask to think
about the sentence: "my pain must end". Undeniably, the
sentence is an expression of compelling ending-desire - the
ending-desire almost forces the subject to cry it out. But it also has a
cognitive content. The sentence is a cry, but not a meaningless cry.
"Must" is the name of an experience content, a compelling desire. (I
would also like to ask: if compelling desire isn't shalling-be, what is?)
By "must" we mean the existence or
presence of a compelling desire. (Not "the existence of my
compelling desire", I claim) Or is the expressed or thought-about sentence
an attempt to order the pain away? And only that? Do we not have any
"must"-experiences? So, I claim: even in normal language use
"must" sometimes refers to a desire. In this point I cannot be
accused (in a
justified way!) of novel terminology. That we say "must" and
"should" mostly in connection to our own desires (if we do), is
perhaps caused by the fact, that the entire compellingness of a desire is
revealed to us only if the desire is our own.
Conceptual questions aside: the most
surprising feature of my prescriptive ethics might be the fact, that it claims
suffering-inducing to be more wrong than the killing (painlessly) of a human.
Feared things are only on second place on my injustice-list. If a murder is
committed secretly, for instance with a poison given to someone in the evening
and killing her in her sleep, it might not even arouse fear in the victim. Do
we have to conclude: this kind of killing is in no way wrong, if the victim has
no close relatives or friends who would grieve for her and if she doesn't do
significant work for the increasing of good in the world?
I honestly think, that inducing suffering is
in itself a greater injustice than killing - even when the victim knows and
fears that she is dying. If a doctor saves her patient's life with a painful
procedure, it is impossible for the patient to ignore her "this pain
should not be"-experience (to not suffer from it). Of course, almost
everyone considers the continuing of her life more important than
relief of a momentary pain, but an intolerable pain is always harder to ignore
than a mere thought, including the thought of one's own death (without which
there is no fear of death).
Still, I don't recommend killing people as a
general practice. In my view, it is useful to keep it criminalized under normal
circumstances (euthanasia is a question for itself). My educated guess is: if
we had to be afraid of being legally killed, our trust towards each other would
crumble. In lack of trust different social (sexual, cooperation-,
business-)relations, that maintain satisfying life, would decrease. This reason
does not, of course, show abortions, or even killing of newborns, wrong.
Another serious problem, that may be seen in
my "fact-morals", is, that it denies our obligations towards the
unconscious (humans). The unconscious don't have desires, "factual
shalling-be:s". This I counter: even fact-morals prohibits (for example) assaults
or wallet-stealing of an unconscious person insofar as we can expect her to
recover consciousness and suffer from the consequences of these actions. It
doesn't prohibit combined robbery and killing of the unconscious, but
legalizing this, too, would (I think) weaken the trust between people and
hamper the functioning of society - at least the illl might think twice, before
agreeing to subject themselves to surgery during anaesthesia. Beside this: even
if I'd defend the right to kill the unconscious or the right to perform
euthanasia on a person against her will (as a cure for occasional
stomach-pains), I believe we could still sleep our nights in peace. A
government, that prohibits painful cancer treatments and permits euthanasia
against a person's will, is soon an ex-government. It should also be safe to
say, more generally: when people have priorities, that conflict with their
"hardest-to-ignore" desires, they will agree on rules, that respect
these priorities, and encourage the recalcitrant "fact-moralist" to
concentrate on her family and hobbies.
Ei kommentteja:
Lähetä kommentti